Of Trains of Reasoning. § 800. The formal logician is only concerned to examine whether the conclusion duly follows from the premisses: he need not concern himself with the truth or falsity of his data. But the premisses of one syllogism may themselves be conclusions deduced from other syllogisms, the premisses of which may in their turn have been established by yet earlier syllogisms. When syllogisms are thus linked together we have what is called a Train of Reasoning. § 801. It is plain that all truths cannot be established by reasoning. For the attempt to do so would involve us in an infinite regress, wherein the number of syllogisms required would increase at each step in a geometrical ratio. To establish the premisses of a given syllogism we should require two preceding syllogisms; to establish their premisses, four; at the next step backwards, eight; at the next, sixteen; and so on ad infinitum. Thus the very possibility of reasoning implies truths that are known to us prior to all reasoning; and, however long a train of reasoning may be, we must ultimately come to truths which are either self-evident or are taken for granted. § 802. Any syllogism which establishes one of the premisses of another is called in reference to that other a Pro-syllogism, while a syllogism which has for one of its premisses the conclusion of another syllogism is called in reference to that other an Epi-syllogism. The Epicheirema. § 803. The name Epicheirema is given to a syllogism with one or both of its premisses supported by a reason. Thus the following is a double epicheirema— All B is A, for it is E. All virtue is praiseworthy, for it promotes the general welfare. § 804. An epicheirema is said to be of the first or second order according as the major or minor premiss is thus supported. The double epicheirema is a combination of the two orders. § 805. An epicheirema, it will be seen, consists of one syllogism fully expressed together with one, or, it may be, two enthymemes (§ 557). In the above instance, if the reasoning which supports the premisses were set forth at full length, we should have, in place of the enthymemes, the two following pro-syllogisms— (i) All E is A. Whatever promotes the general welfare is praiseworthy. (2) All F is B. Whatever prompts men to postpone self to others is a virtue. § 806. The enthymemes in the instance above given are both of the first order, having the major premiss suppressed. But there is nothing to prevent one or both of them from being of the second order— All B is A, because all F is. All Mahometans are fanatics, because all Monotheists are. Here it is the minor premiss in each syllogism that is suppressed, namely, (1) All Mahometans are Monotheists. (2) These men are Persians. The Sorites. § 807. The Sorites is the neatest and most compendious form that can be assumed by a train of reasoning. § 808. It is sometimes more appropriately called the chain-argument, and map be defined as— A train of reasoning, in which one premiss of each epi-syllogism is This is its inner essence. § 809. In its outward form it may be described as—A series of propositions, each of which has one term in common with that which preceded it, while in the conclusion one of the terms in the last proposition becomes either subject or predicate to one of the terms in the first. § 810. A sorites may be either— (1) Progressive, or (2) Regressive. Progressive Sorites. All A is B. Regressive Sorites. All D is E. § 811. The usual form is the progressive; so that the sorites is commonly described as a series of propositions in which the predicate of each becomes the subject of the next, while in the conclusion the last predicate is affirmed or denied of the first subject. The regressive form, however, exactly reverses these attributes; and would require to be described as a series of propositions, in which the subject of each becomes the predicate of the next, while in the conclusion the first predicate is affirmed or denied of the last subject. § 812. The regressive sorites, it will be observed, consists of the same propositions as the progressive one, only written in reverse order. Why then, it may be asked, do we give a special name to it, though we do not consider a syllogism different, if the minor premiss happens to precede the major? It is because the sorites is not a mere series of propositions, but a compressed train of reasoning; and the two trains of reasoning may be resolved into their component syllogisms in such a manner as to exhibit a real difference between them. § 813. The Progressive Sorites is a train of reasoning in which the minor premiss of each epi-syllogism is supported by a pro-syllogism, while the major is taken for granted. § 814. The Regressive Sorites is a train of reasoning in which the major premiss of each epi-syllogism is supported by a pro-syllogism, while the minor is taken for granted. Progressive Sorites. (2) All C is D. (3) All D is E. Regressive Sorites. (2) All C is E. (3) All B is E. § 815. Here is a concrete example of the two kinds of sorites, resolved each into its component syllogisms— Progressive Sorites. All Bideford men are Devonshire men. (1) All Devonshire men are Englishmen. (2) All Englishmen are Teutons. (3) All Teutons are Aryans. Regressive Sorites. All Teutons are Aryans. (1) All Teutons are Aryans. (2) All Englishmen are Aryans. (3) All Devonshiremen are Aryans. § 816. When expanded, the sorites is found to contain as many syllogisms as there are propositions intermediate between the first and the last. This is evident also on inspection by counting the number of middle terms. § 817. In expanding the progressive form we have to commence with the second proposition of the sorites as the major premiss of the first syllogism. In the progressive form the subject of the conclusion is the same in all the syllogisms; in the regressive form the predicate is the same. In both the same series of means, or middle terms, is employed, the difference lying in the extremes that are compared with one another through them. [Illustration] § 818. It is apparent from the figure that in the progressive form we work from within outwards, in the regressive form from without inwards. In the former we first employ the term 'Devonshiremen' as a mean to connect 'Bideford men' with 'Englishmen'; next we employ 'Englishmen' as a mean to connect the same subject 'Bideford men' with the wider term 'Teutons'; and, lastly, we employ 'Teutons' as a mean to connect the original subject 'Bideford men' with the ultimate predicate 'Ayrans.' § 819. Reversely, in the regressive form we first use 'Teutons' as a mean whereby to bring 'Englishmen' under 'Aryans'; next we use 'Englishmen' as a mean whereby to bring 'Devonshiremen' under the dame predicate 'Aryans'; and, lastly, we use 'Devonshiremen' as a mean whereby to bring the ultimate subject 'Bideford men' under the original predicate 'Aryans.' § 820. A sorites may be either Regular or Irregular. § 821. In the regular form the terms which connect each proposition in the series with its predecessor, that is to say, the middle terms, maintain a fixed relative position; so that, if the middle term be subject in one, it will always be predicate in the other, and vice versÂ. In the irregular form this symmetrical arrangement is violated. § 822. The syllogisms which compose a regular sorites, whether progressive or regressive, will always be in the first figure. In the irregular sorites the syllogisms may fall into different figures. § 823. For the regular sorites the following rules may be laid down. (1) Only one premiss can be particular, namely, the first, if the (2) Only one premiss can be negative, namely, the last, if the sorites be progressive, the first, if it be regressive. § 824. Proof of the Rules for the Regular Sorites. (1) In the progressive sorites the proposition which stands first is the only one which appears as a minor premiss in the expanded form. Each of the others is used in its turn as a major. If any proposition, therefore, but the first were particular, there would be a particular major, which involves undistributed middle, if the minor be affirmative, as it must be in the first figure. In the regressive sorites, if any proposition except the last were particular, we should have a particular conclusion in the syllogism in which it occurred as a premiss, and so a particular major in the next syllogism, which again is inadmissible, as involving undistributed middle. (2) In the progressive sorites, if any premiss before the last were negative, we should have a negative conclusion in the syllogism in which it occurs. This would necessitate a negative minor in the next syllogism, which is inadmissible in the first figure, as involving illicit process of the major. In the regressive sorites the proposition which stands first is the only one which appears as a major premiss in the expanded form. Each of the others is used in its turn as a minor. If any premiss, therefore, but the first were negative, we should have a negative minor in the first figure, which involves illicit process of the major. § 825. The rules above given do not apply to the irregular sorites, except so far as that only one premiss can be particular and only one negative, which follows from the general rules of syllogism. But there is nothing to prevent any one premiss from being particular or any one premiss from being negative, as the subjoined examples will show. Both the instances chosen belong to the progressive order of sorites. (1) Barbara. All B is A. [Illustration] (2) Disamis. (3) Darii. (1) Barbara. All A is B. [Illustration] (2) Cesare. (3) Camestres. § 826. A chain argument may be composed consisting of conjunctive instead of simple propositions. This is subject to the same laws as the simple sorites, to which it is immediately reducible. Progressive. Regressive. |