Of Compound Forms of Immediate Inference. § 503. Having now treated of the three simple forms of immediate inference, we go on to speak of the compound forms, and first of Conversion by Negation. § 504. When A and O have been permuted, they become respectively E and I, and, in this form, admit of simple conversion. We have here two steps of inference: but the process may be performed at a single stroke, and is then known as Conversion by Negation. Thus from 'All A is B' we may infer 'No not-B is A,' and again from 'Some A is not B' we may infer 'Some not-B is A.' The nature of these inferences will be seen better in concrete examples. § 505. (A) All poets are imaginative. (O) Some parsons are not clerical. § 506. The above inferences, when analysed, will be found to resolve themselves into two steps, namely, (1) Permutation. (2) Simple Conversion. (A) All A is B. (O) Some A is not B. § 507. The term conversion by negation has been arbitrarily limited to the exact inferential procedure of permutation followed by simple conversion. Hence it necessarily applies only to A and 0 propositions, since these when permuted become E and 1, which admit of simple conversion; whereas E and 1 themselves are permuted into A and 0, which do not. There seems to be no good reason, however, why the term 'conversion by negation' should be thus restricted in its meaning; instead of being extended to the combination of permutation with conversion, no matter in what order the two processes may be performed. If this is not done, inferences quite as legitimate as those which pass under the title of conversion by negation are left without a name. § 508. From E and 1 inferences may be elicited as follows— (E) No A is B. (I) Some A is B. (E) No good actions are unbecoming. (I) Some poetical persons are logicians. Or, taking a privative term for our subject, Some unpractical persons are statesmen. § 509. When the inferences just given are analysed, it will be found that the process of simple conversion precedes that of permutation. § 510. In the case of the E proposition a compound inference can be drawn even in the original order of the processes, No A is B. No one who employs bribery is honest. The inference here, it must be remembered, does not refer to matter of fact, but means that one of the possible forms of dishonesty among men is that of employing bribery. § 511. If we analyse the preceding, we find that the second step is conversion by limitation. No A is B. § 512. From A again an inference can be drawn in the reverse order of conversion per accidens followed by permutation— All A is B. All ingenuous persons are agreeable. § 513. The intermediate link between the above two propositions is the converse per accidens of the first—'Some B is A.' This inference, however, coincides with that from 1 (§ 508), as the similar inference from E (§ 510) coincides with that from 0 (§ 506). § 514. All these inferences agree in the essential feature of combining permutation with conversion, and should therefore be classed under a common name. § 515. Adopting then this slight extension of the term, we define conversion by negation as—A form of conversion in which the converse differs in quality from the convertend, and has the contradictory of one of the original terms. § 516. A still more complex form of immediate inference is known as Conversion by Contraposition. This mode of inference assumes the following form— All A is B. All human beings are fallible. § 517. This will be found to resolve itself on analysis into three steps of inference in the following order— (1) Permutation. (2) Simple Conversion. (3) Permutation. § 518. Let us verify this statement by performing the three steps. All A is B. All Englishmen are Aryans. § 519. Conversion by contraposition may be complicated in appearance by the occurrence of a negative term in the subject or predicate or both, e.g. All not-A is B. Again, All A is not-B. Lastly, All not-A is not-B. § 520. The following practical rule will be found of use for the right performing of the process— Transpose the subject and predicate, and substitute for each its § 521. As concrete illustrations of the above forms of inference we may take the following— All the men on this board that are not white are red. Again, All compulsory labour is inefficient. Lastly, All inexpedient acts are unjust. § 522. Conversion by contraposition may be said to rest on the following principle— If one class be wholly contained in another, whatever is external to [Illustration] § 523. The same principle may be expressed intensively as follows:— If an attribute belongs to the whole of a subject, whatever fails to exhibit that attribute does not come under the subject. § 524. This statement contemplates conversion by contraposition only in reference to the A proposition, to which the process has hitherto been confined. Logicians seem to have overlooked the fact that conversion by contraposition is as applicable to the O as to the A proposition, though, when expressed in symbols, it presents a more clumsy appearance. Some A is not B. Some wholesome things are not pleasant. § 525. The above admits of analysis in exactly the same way as the same process when applied to the A proposition. Some A is not B. The result, as in the case of the A proposition, is the converse by negation of the original proposition permuted. § 526. Contraposition may also be applied to the E proposition by the use of conversion per accidens in the place of simple conversion. But, owing to the limitation of quantity thus effected, the result arrived at is the same as in the case of the O proposition. Thus from 'No wholesome things are pleasant' we could draw the same inference as before. Here is the process in symbols, when expanded. No A is B. § 527. In its unanalysed form conversion by contraposition may be defined generally as—A form of conversion in which both subject and predicate are replaced by their contradictories. § 528. Conversion by contraposition differs in several respects from conversion by negation. (1) In conversion by negation the converse differs in quality from the convertend: whereas in conversion by contraposition the quality of the two is the same. (2) In conversion by negation we employ the contradictory either of the subject or predicate, but in conversion by contraposition we employ the contradictory of both. (3) Conversion by negation involves only two steps of immediate inference: conversion by contraposition three. § 529. Conversion by contraposition cannot be applied to the ordinary E proposition except by limitation (§ 526). From 'No A is B' we cannot infer 'No not-B is not-A.' For, if we could, the contradictory of the latter, namely, 'Some not-B is not-A' would be false. But it is manifest that this is not necessarily false. For when one term is excluded from another, there must be numerous individuals which fall under neither of them, unless it should so happen that one of the terms is the direct contradictory of the other, which is clearly not conveyed by the form of the expression 'No A is B. 'No A is not-A' stands alone among E propositions in admitting of full conversion by contraposition, and the form of that is the same after it as before. § 530. Nor can conversion by contraposition be applied at all to I. [Illustration] From 'Some A is B' we cannot infer that 'Some not-B is not-A.' For though the proposition holds true as a matter of fact, when A and B are in part mutually exclusive, yet this is not conveyed by the form of the expression. It may so happen that B is wholly contained under A, while A itself contains everything. In this case it will be true that 'No not-B is not-A,' which contradicts the attempted inference. Thus from the proposition 'Some things are substances' it cannot be inferred that 'Some not-substances are not-things,' for in this case the contradictory is true that 'No not-substances are not-things'; and unless an inference is valid in every case, it is not formally valid at all. § 531. It should be noticed that in the case of the [nu] proposition immediate inferences are possible by mere contraposition without conversion. All A is all B. For example, if all the equilateral triangles are all the equiangular, we know at once that all non-equilateral triangles are also non-equiangular. § 532. The principle upon which this last kind of inference rests is that when two terms are co-extensive, whatever is excluded from the one is excluded also from the other. |