CHAPTER XII. MENTAL EVOLUTION.

Previous

The phrase "mental evolution" clearly implies the existence of somewhat concerning which evolution can be predicated; and the adjective "mental" further implies that this somewhat is that which we term "mind." What is this mind which is said to be evolved? And out of what has it been evolved? Can we say that matter, when it reaches the complexity of the grey cortex of the brain, becomes at last self-conscious? May we say that mind is evolved from matter, and that when the dance of molecules reaches a certain intensity and intricacy consciousness is developed? I conceive not.

"If a material element," says Mr. A. R. Wallace,[JY] "or a combination of a thousand material elements in a molecule, are alike unconscious, it is impossible for us to believe that the mere addition of one, two, or a thousand other material elements to form a more complex molecule could in any way tend to produce a self-conscious existence. The things are radically distinct. To say that mind is a product or function of protoplasm, or of its molecular changes, is to use words to which we can attach no clear conception. You cannot have in the whole what does not exist in any of the parts; and those who argue thus should put forth a definite conception of matter, with clearly enunciated properties, and show that the necessary result of a certain complex arrangement of the elements or atoms of that matter will be the production of self-consciousness. There is no escape from this dilemma—either all matter is conscious, or consciousness is something distinct from matter; and in the latter case, its presence in material forms is a proof of the existence of conscious beings, outside of and independent of what we term 'matter.'"

There is a central core of truth in Mr. Wallace's argument which I hold to be beyond question, though I completely dissent from the conclusion which he draws from it. I do not believe that the existence of conscious beings, outside of and independent of what we term "matter," is a tenable scientific hypothesis. In which case, Mr. Wallace will reply, "You are driven on to the other horn of the dilemma, and must hold the preposterous view that all matter is conscious."

Now, I venture to think that the use here of the word "conscious" is prejudicial to the fair consideration of the view which I hold in common with many others of far greater insight than I can lay claim to. And it seems to me that we cannot fairly discuss this question without the introduction of terms which, from their novelty, are devoid of the inevitable implications associated with "mind" and "consciousness" and their correlative adjectives. Such terms, therefore, I venture to suggest, not with a view to their general acceptance, but to enable me to set forth, without arousing at the outset antagonistic prejudice, that hypothesis which alone, as it seems to me, meets the conditions of the case.

According to the hypothesis that is known as the monistic hypothesis, the so-called connection between the molecular changes in the brain and the concomitant states of consciousness is assumed to be identity. Professor Huxley suggested the term "neuroses" for the molecular changes in the brain, and "psychoses" for the concomitant states of consciousness. According to materialism, psychosis is a product of neurosis; but according to monism, neither is psychosis a product of neurosis, nor is neurosis a product of psychosis, but neurosis is psychosis. They are identical. What an external observer might perceive as a neurosis of my brain, I should at the same moment be feeling as a psychosis. The neurosis is the outer or objective aspect; the psychosis is the inner or subjective aspect.

It is almost impossible to illustrate this assumption by any physical analogies. Perhaps the best is that of a curved surface. The convex side is quite different from the concave side. But we cannot say that the concavity is produced by the convexity, or that the convexity is caused by the concavity. The convex and the concave are simply different aspects of the same curved surface. So, too, are molecular brain-changes (neuroses) and the concomitant states of consciousness (psychoses) simply different aspects of the same waves on the troubled sea of being. Again, we may liken the brain-changes to spoken or written words, and the states of consciousness to the meaning which underlies them. The spoken word is, from the physical point of view, a mere shudder of sound in the air; but it is also, from the conceptual point of view, a fragment of analytic thought.

Now, we believe that the particular kind of molecular motion which we call neurosis, or brain-action, has been evolved. Evolved from what? From other and simpler modes of molecular motion. Complex neuroses have been evolved from less complex neuroses; these from simple neuroses; these, again, from organic modes of motion which can no longer be called neuroses at all; and these, once more, from modes of motion which can no longer be called organic. And from what have psychoses, or states of consciousness, been evolved? Complex psychoses have been evolved from less complex psychoses; these from simple psychoses; these, again, from—what? We are stopped for want of words to express our meaning. We believe that psychoses have been evolved. Evolved from what? From other and simpler modes of—something which answers on the subjective side to motion. We can hardly say "of consciousness;" for consciousness answers to a particular mode of motion called neurosis. So that unless we are prepared to say that all modes of motion are neuroses, we can hardly say that all modes of that which answers on the subjective side to motion are conscious. I shall venture, therefore, to coin a word[JZ] to meet my present need.

It is generally admitted that physical phenomena, including those which we call physiological, can be explained (or are explicable) in terms of energy. It is also generally admitted that consciousness is something distinct from, nay, belonging to a wholly different phenomenal order from, energy. And it is further generally admitted that consciousness is nevertheless in some way closely, if not indissolubly, associated with special manifestations of energy in the nerve-centres of the brain. Now, we call manifestations of energy "kinetic" manifestations, and we use the term "kinesis" for physical manifestations of this order. Similarly, we may call concomitant manifestations of the mental or conscious order "metakinetic," and may use the term "metakinesis" for all manifestations belonging to this phenomenal order. According to the monistic hypothesis, every mode of kinesis has its concomitant mode of metakinesis, and when the kinetic manifestations assume the form of the molecular processes in the human brain, the metakinetic manifestations assume the form of human consciousness. I am, therefore, not prepared to accept the horn of Mr. Wallace's dilemma in the form in which he states it. All matter is not conscious, because consciousness is the metakinetic concomitant of a highly specialized order of kinesis. But every kinesis has an associated metakinesis; and parallel to the evolution of organic and neural kinesis there has been an evolution of metakinetic manifestations culminating in conscious thought.

Paraphrasing the words of Professor Max MÜller,[KA] I say, "Like Descartes, like Spinoza, like Leibnitz, like NoirÉ, I require two orders of phenomena only, but I define them differently, namely, as kinesis and metakinesis. According to these two attributes of the noumenal, philosophy has to do with two streams of evolution—the subjective and the objective. Neither of them can be said to be prior.... The two streams of evolution run parallel, or, more correctly, the two are one stream, looked at from two opposite shores." And again,[KB] "Like NoirÉ, I would go hand-in-hand with Spinoza, and carry away with me this permanent truth, that metakinesis can never be the product of kinesis (materialism), nor kinesis the product of metakinesis (spiritualism), but that the two are inseparable, like two sides of one and the same substance."

According to this view, the two distinct phenomenal orders, the kinetic and the metakinetic, are distinct only as being different phenomenal manifestations of the same noumenal series. Matter, the unknown substance[KC] of kinetic manifestations, disappears as unnecessary; spirit, the unknown substance of metakinetic manifestations, also disappears; both are merged in the unknown substance of being—unknown, that is to say, in itself and apart from its objective and subjective manifestations.

It will, no doubt, be objected that the final identity of neuroses and psychoses is an assumption. It is pure assumption, it will be said, that these molecular nervous processes, and those percepts and emotions which are their concomitants, are simply different aspects, outer and inner, objective and subjective, physiological and psychological, of the same noumenal series. This must fully and freely be admitted. Any and every explanation of the connection of mind and body is based on an assumption. The common-place view of two distinct entities, a mind which can act on the body and a body which influences the mind, is a pure assumption. The philosophic view, that there are two entities, body and mind, that neither can act on the other, but that there is a pre-established harmony between the activities of the one and the activities of the other, is, again, a pure assumption. The materialistic view, that matter becomes at last self-conscious, is a pure assumption. The idealistic view, that the world of phenomena has no existence save as a fiction of my own mind, is, once more, a pure assumption. It is not a question of making or of not making an initial assumption; that we must do in any case. The question is—Which assumption yields the most consistent and harmonious results?

Again, an answer will, no doubt, be demanded by some people to the question—How does that which, objectively considered, is neurosis become subjectively felt as psychosis? Is not the identification of neurosis and psychosis a begging of the question, unless the how, the modus operandi, is explained? If, in the latter query, by "begging the question" the adoption of an initial assumption is meant, I have already answered it in the affirmative. To the direct question—How does the objective neurosis become conscious as a subjective psychosis?—while freely admitting that I do not know, I enter the protest that it is philosophically an illegitimate question; for an answer is impossible without transcending consciousness. An illustration will, perhaps, make my meaning clear. Suppose that a sentient being be enclosed within a sphere of opaque but translucent ground glass, into the substance of which there are wrought certain characters. Suppose that external to this there is another similar but larger sphere, similarly inscribed, and that a second sentient being is enclosed in the space between the two spheres. By an attentive study of the two spheres, this second sentient being arrives at the conclusion that the markings on the convex surface of the inner sphere answer to the markings on the concave surface of the outer sphere; and he is led to the conviction that what he sees as markings on the convex, the being within the sphere sees as markings on the concave. He is, however, perplexed by the question—How can this be? He is acquainted with a certain inner surface and a certain outer surface. He is led to correlate the markings of the one with the markings of the other. But the question how the two can have such different aspects is beyond his solution. Puzzle as he may, he can never solve it. It can only be solved (and how simple then the solution!) by a being outside both spheres, who can see what the enclosed being, "cabin'd, cribb'd, confined," could never see, namely, that the characters were wrought in the translucent glass of the spheres. By which parable, imperfect as it is, I would teach that we can never learn how kinetic manifestations have a metakinetic aspect without getting outside ourselves to view kinesis and metakinesis from an independent standpoint. Or, in the words of Sir W. R. Hamilton,[KD] "How consciousness in general is possible; and how, in particular, the consciousness of self and the consciousness of something different from self are possible ... these questions are equally unphilosophical, as they suppose the possibility of a faculty exterior to consciousness and conversant about its operations."

The only course open to us, then, in this difficult but important problem is to make certain assumptions, and see how far a consistent hypothesis may be based upon them. I make, therefore, the following assumptions: First, that there is a noumenal system of "things in themselves" of which all phenomena, whether kinetic or metakinetic, are manifestations. Secondly, that whenever in the curve of noumenal sequences kinetic manifestations (convexities) appear, there appear also concomitant metakinetic manifestations (concavities). Thirdly, that when kinetic manifestations assume the integrated and co-ordinated complexity of the nerve-processes in certain ganglia of the human brain, the metakinetic manifestations assume the integrated and co-ordinated complexity of human consciousness. Fourthly, that what is called "mental evolution" is the metakinetic aspect of what is called brain or interneural evolution.

It would require far more space than I can here command to deal adequately with these assumptions, and meet the objections which have been and are likely to be raised against them. I must content myself with drawing attention to one or two which seem at once obvious and yet easily met.

It may be asked—What advantage has such a view over realistic materialism? Why not assume that neural processes, when they reach a certain complexity, give rise to or produce consciousness?

First of all, I think, the objection raised by Mr. Wallace, in the passage before quoted, to materialism is unanswerable. Secondly, realistic materialism ignores the fact that kinetic manifestations for us human-folk are phenomena of consciousness. To this we will return presently. Thirdly, realistic materialism, and any view which regards the physical series as one which is independent of the psychical accompaniments, and which regards consciousness as in any sense a by-product of neural processes, are open to an objection which was forcibly stated by the late Professor Herbert.[KE] "It is clearly impossible," he says, "for those ... who teach that consciousness is [a by-product and] never the cause of physical change, to dispute that the actions, words and gestures of every individual of the human race would have been exactly what they have been in the absence of mind; had mind been wanting [had the by-product never emerged], the same empires would have risen and fallen, the same battles would have been fought and won, the same literature, the same masterpieces of painting and music would have been produced, the same religious rites would have been performed, and the same indications of friendship and affection given. To this absurdity physical science [realistic materialism] stands committed." I believe that Professor Herbert's argument, of which this passage is a summary, is, as against realistic materialism, sound and unanswerable. Finally, as Professor Max MÜller has well observed,[KF] "Materialism may in one sense be said to be a grammatical blunder; it is a misapplication of a word which can be used in an oblique sense only, but which materialists use in the nominative. In another sense it is a logical blunder, because it rests on a confusion between the objective and the subjective. Matter can never be a subject, it can never know, because the name was framed to signify what is the object of our knowledge or what can be known." Materialism, then, for more than one sufficient reason, stands condemned.

It should be stated, however, that Professor Herbert seems to regard the monistic view I am advocating as committed to the absurdity indicated in the passage I have quoted. I am convinced that he was here in error. Indeed, he seems to have failed to see the full bearing of the monistic hypothesis; for while he combats it, he comes very near adopting it himself. With this, however, I have no concern. I have only to show that, on the assumptions above set down, we are not committed to the "absurdity" of supposing that intelligence and consciousness have had no influence on the course of events in organic evolution—that they have only felt the inevitable sequence of physical phenomena without in any way influencing it. According to the monistic hypothesis, kinesis and metakinesis are co-ordinate. The physiologist may explain all the activities of men and animals in terms of kinesis. The psychologist may explain all the thoughts and emotions of man in terms of metakinesis. They are studying the different phenomenal aspects of the same noumenal sequences. It is just as absurd to say that kinetic manifestations would have been the same in the absence of metakinesis, as to say that the metakinetic manifestations, the thoughts and emotions, would have been the same in the absence of kinesis. It is just as absurd to say that the physical series would have been the same in the absence of mind, as to say that the mental series would have been the same in the absence of bodily organization. For on this view consciousness is no mere by-product of neural processes, but is simply one aspect of them. You cannot abstract (except in thought and by analysis) metakinesis from kinesis; for when you have taken away the one, you have taken the other also. To speak of the organic activities being conceivably the same in the absence of consciousness, is like saying that the outer curve of a soap-bubble would be the same in the absence of the inner curve. Whatever hypothetical existences this statement may be true of, it assuredly is not true of soap-bubbles.

To pass on from this point to another, it is possible—I trust not probable, but still not impossible—that some one may say, "But how, on this view, can perception be accounted for? Granted that in the neural processes of the individual organism kinesis is accompanied by those metakinetic manifestations which we term 'consciousness,' how will this account for our perception of a distant object? Yonder scarlet geranium is a centre of kinetic manifestations; it is fifty yards and more away. How can I here, by any metakinetic process, perceive the kinesis that is going on out there?"

For one who can ask this question, I have written the chapter on "Mental Processes in Man," and have used the term "construct," in vain. In vain have I endeavoured to explain that the seat of all mental processes is somewhere within the brain; in vain have I indicated the nature of localization and outward projection; in vain have I reiterated that the object is a thing we construct through a (metakinetic) activity of the mind; in vain have I insisted that our knowledge is merely symbolic of the noumenal existence; and perhaps in vain shall I again endeavour to make my meaning clear.

When we say that we perceive an object, the mental process (perception) is the metakinetic equivalent of certain kinetic changes among the brain-molecules. The object, as an object (as a phenomenon or appearance), is there generated. As before stated, I assume the existence of a noumenal system of which the noumenal existence, symbolized as object, is a part. But what we term the object is a certain phase of metakinesis accompanying certain kinetic nerve-processes in the brain. In other words, phenomena are states of consciousness, and cannot, for the percipient, be anything else.

"It comes to this, then," an idealist will interpose: "states of consciousness are metakinetic; phenomena are states of consciousness; therefore phenomena are metakinetic. Your kinesis vanishes, and you are one with us, a pure idealist."

Before showing wherein I am not a pure idealist, let me state why I am not. For the pure idealist, phenomena being states of consciousness, and nothing more, the world around resolves itself into an individual dream. Were I to hold this view, this pen which I hold, this table at which I write, the spreading trees outside my window, my little sons whose merry voices I can hear in the garden, my very body and limbs, all are merely states of my own consciousness. This I am not prepared to accept. Do what I will, I cannot believe that such an interpretation of the facts is true.

For this reason I make my first assumption that there is a noumenal system of things in themselves, of which all phenomena, whether kinetic or metakinetic, are manifestations. I differ from the pure idealist in that I believe that phenomena, besides being states of consciousness, have another, namely, a kinetic, aspect. What are for me states of consciousness are for you neural processes in my brain. These are, again, for you states of consciousness; but still for some one else they are kinetic processes. And an ordinary extraneous object, like this table, is the phenomenal aspect to me of a noumenal existence; and since that noumenal existence appears to you also in like phenomenal guise, the table is an object for you as well as for me, and not only for us, but for all sentient beings similarly constituted. The world we live in is a world of phenomena; and it has a phenomenal reality every whit as valid as the noumenal reality which underlies it. And that phenomenal reality has two aspects—an inner aspect as metakinesis, and an outer aspect as kinesis.

I must not here further develop the manner in which the hypothesis of monism presents itself to my mind. I will only, before passing on to consider mental or metakinetic evolution, draw passing attention to two matters. We have seen that Professor Hering and Mr. Samuel Butler have suggested "organic memory" as a conception useful for the comprehension of embryonic reconstruction in development and other such matters (see p.62). On the hypothesis of monism, this may be regarded as a kinetic manifestation of that which in memory rises to the metakinetic level of consciousness.

The other matter is of far wider import. Monism affords a consistent and comprehensible theory of the ego, or conscious self—that which endures amid the flux and reflux of our conscious states. The ego, or self, is that metakinetic unity which answers to, or is the inner aspect of, the kinetic unity of the organism.[KG] Only here and there, in fleeting and changing series, does the metakinesis rise to the level of consciousness. But the metakinetic unity is as completely one, indivisible, and enduring, as is the physical organism which is its kinetic counterpart. No one questions that there is an enduring organism of which certain visible activities are occasional manifestations; no one who has adequately grasped the teachings of monism can question that the enduring ego, of which certain states of consciousness are occasional manifestations, is the metakinetic equivalent of the organic kinesis. This solution of a problem which baffles alike materialists and idealists is, as it seems to me, as satisfactory as it is simple.

And now let us pass on to consider the question of mental or metakinetic evolution. What, on the principles above laid down, can we be said to know or have learnt about it?

The inevitable isolation of the individual mind has long been recognized. "Such is the nature of spirit, or that which acts," says Bishop Berkeley, "that it cannot be itself perceived, but only by the effects that it produceth." "Thinking things, as such," writes Kant, "can never occur in the outward phenomena; we can have no outward perception of their thoughts, consciousness, desires; for all this is the domain of the inward sense." How comes it, then, that there is nothing of which, practically speaking, we are more firmly convinced than that our neighbours have each a consciousness more or less similar to our own? Certain it is that no one can come into sensible contact with his brother's personality and essential spirit. My brother's soul can never stand to me in the relation of object. Subject he never can be to any but himself. What, then, is he—his metakinetic self, not his kinetic material body—to me? In Clifford's convenient phrase, he is an eject. And what is an eject? An eject is a more or less modified image of myself, that I see mirrored, as in a glass darkly, in the human-folk around me. Into every human brother I breathe the spirit of this eject, and he becomes henceforth to me a living soul. Or, if this mode of presentation does not meet with approval, I will say that an eject is that metakinetic unity I infer as identically associated with the organic and kinetic unity of my brother's living body. And I base the close metakinetic correspondence that I infer on the close kinetic correspondence that I observe. But since the only form or kind of metakinesis that I know is that of human self-conscious personality, it is certain that the metakinetic eject is an image of myself; it is and must be, in a word, anthropomorphic.

Too much stress can scarcely, I think, be laid on the human, nay, even the individual, nature of the eject. All other-mind I am bound to think of in terms of my own mind. The men and women I see around me are like curved mirrors, in which I see an altered reflection of my own mental features. By certain signs I may be able to infer in this or that human mirror graces or imperfections that I lack. But throughout my survey of human nature, every estimate of intellectual or moral elevation or degradation that I form must ever be measured in terms of my own subjective base-line. My conception of humanity must always be, not only anthropomorphic, but idiomorphic.

Once more, let it be remembered that the metakinesis that rises to the level of consciousness is that which forms the inner aspect of the neural kinesis of my brain or yours. For each of us, then, that metakinesis is the only possible metakinesis which we can know as such and at first-hand. And for the pure idealist it is the only metakinesis which he can know at all. Not so with us. We have assumed a noumenal system of "things in themselves," of which all phenomena, whether kinetic or metakinetic, are manifestations. We have assumed that kinesis cannot emerge into the light of being without casting its inseparable metakinetic shadow. We have assumed that when the kinetic manifestations assume the integrated and co-ordinated complexity of nerve-processes in certain ganglia of the human brain, the metakinetic manifestations assume the integrated and co-ordinated complexity of human consciousness. Human physiology is teaching us more clearly every day that all human activities are, physically speaking, the outcome of neural processes. Such neural processes are in us conscious. Therefore, granting our assumptions, the conclusion that my neighbour is a conscious self, just as I am, is not only legitimate, but (as we see from the daily conduct of men) inevitable. In other words, certain kinetic phenomena have for us inevitable metakinetic implications.

Now, when we pass from man to the lower animals, the metakinetic implications become progressively less inevitable and less forcible as the kinesis becomes more dissimilar from that which obtains in the human organism. The only metakinesis that we know directly is our own human consciousness. In terms of this we have to interpret all other forms of metakinesis.

It is unnecessary to go over again the ground that has already been covered in previous chapters, in which we have endeavoured to give some account of what seem to us the legitimate inferences concerning the mental processes in animals. The point on which I wish here to insist is that, outside ourselves, we can only know metakinesis in and through its correlative kinesis. Underlying kinetic evolution, we see that, on the hypothesis of monism, there must have been metakinetic evolution. But of this mental or metakinetic evolution we neither have nor can have independent evidence. Such evolution is the inevitable monistic corollary from kinetic evolution. More than this it is not and cannot be. And only on the monistic hypothesis, as it seems to me, is it admissible to believe in mental evolution,[KH] properly so called.

But does not, it may be asked, the hypothesis of monism, if carried to its logical conclusion, involve the belief in a world-consciousness on the one hand, and a crystal-consciousness on the other? If, according to the hypothesis, every form of kinesis has also its metakinetic aspect, "must we not maintain," in the words of Mr. J. A. Symonds, "that the universe being in one rhythm, things less highly organized than man possess consciousness in the degree of their descent, less acute than man's? Must we not also surmise that ascending scales of existence, more highly organized, of whom we are at present ignorant, are endowed with consciousness superior to man's? Is it incredible that the globe on which we live is vastly more conscious of itself than we are of ourselves; and that the cells which compose our corporeal frame are gifted with a separate consciousness of a simpler kind than ours?" To such questions W. K. Clifford replied with an emphatic negative. "Unless we can show," he said, as interpreted by Mr. Romanes,[KI] "in the disposition of the heavenly bodies some morphological resemblance to the structure of a human brain, we are precluded from rationally entertaining any probability that self-conscious volition belongs to the universe."

I conceive that both parties, opposed as they seem, are logically right; and I venture to think that the terms I have suggested will help us here. Mr. Symonds used the word "consciousness" to signify metakinesis in general; Clifford used it to signify that particular kind of metakinesis which in the human brain rises to the level of consciousness. Not only is it not inconceivable, but it is a logical necessity on the hypothesis of monism, that answering to the kinetic rhythm of the universe there is a metakinetic rhythm; but unless the gyrations of the spheres have some kinetic resemblance to the dance of molecules in the human brain, the metakinesis cannot be inferred to be similar to the consciousness of man.

Similarly, with regard to the supposed self-consciousness of the so-called social organism. Mr. Romanes, in his article on "The World as an Eject,"[KJ] leads up to his conception of a world-eject through the conception of a society-eject—an eject, he tells us, that, for aught that any one of its constituent personalities can prove to the contrary, may possess self-conscious personality of the most vivid character. Its constituent human minds may be born into it, and die out of it, as do the constituent cells of the human body; it may feel the throes of war and famine, rejoice in the comforts of peace and plenty; it may appreciate the growth of civilization in its passage from childhood to maturity.

This, of course, may be so; or it may not. Who can tell? But Clifford was on firm monistic ground when he maintained that, unless the kinesis be similar, we have no grounds for inferring similarity of metakinesis.

The study of kinesis leads us to recognize different kinds or modes of its manifestation. There is one mode of kinesis in the circling of the planets around the sun, another mode of kinesis in the orderly evolutions of a great army, another mode in the throb of a great printing-press; there is one mode of kinesis in the quivering molecules of the intensely heated sun, another in the wire that flashes our thought to America, and yet another in the molecular vibrations of the human brain. All are of the same order, all are kinetic. But they differ so widely in mode that each requires separate, patient, and long-continued study. So is it, we may conclude, with metakinesis. There may be, nay, there must be, many modes. But our knowledge is confined to one mode—that in which the metakinesis assumes the form of human consciousness.

I have been led to discuss this matter in order further to indicate the inevitable limits of our knowledge of metakinetic evolution. Our conclusions may be thus summarized: First, we can know directly only one product of metakinetic evolution—that revealed in our own consciousness. Secondly, the process of metakinetic evolution must be reached, if reached at all, indirectly through a study of kinetic evolution. Thirdly, we have no right to infer a mode of metakinesis analogous to human consciousness, unless the mode of kinesis is analogous to that which is observed in neural processes. And, fourthly, the closer the kinetic resemblance we observe, the closer the metakinetic resemblance we may infer.


The last point we have to notice, and it is by no means an unimportant one, is that, just as the kinetic evolution of the organism must be studied in reference to its kinetic environment, so, too, must the metakinetic evolution of mind be studied in reference to its metakinetic or mental environment.

Of course, in ordinary speech, and even in careful scientific description, we are forced, if we would avoid pedantry, to skip backwards and forwards from the kinetic to the metakinetic. We speak of a kinetic cow giving rise to metakinetic fear, and this determining certain kinetic activities. Why we thus interpose a mental link in a physical series has already been explained. The physical cow we know, the physical activities we know, the physical neuroses we scarcely know at all. On the other hand, fear we have ourselves experienced, and know well. Hence we introduce the mental link that we know in place of the physical link of which we are ignorant. And there can be no harm in our doing so when we are working on the practical, and not the philosophical plane. But when we are striving to go deeper, and are employing that gift of analysis which is man's prerogative, in order to proceed to a higher and more complete synthesis,—then we must be careful to keep separate those processes which analysis discloses to be distinct. And I repeat that, on the philosophical plane of thought, we must remember that metakineses are determined by other metakineses, and by them alone.

The reader who has kept his head among these slippery places will at once see that this is and must be so; for, as we have already seen (p.474), all phenomena are states of consciousness, whatever else they may also be. The cow, as a phenomenon, is a construct, a product of mental activity, and woven out of states of consciousness. For the pure idealist she is this and nothing more. But for us she is a real external entity, manifested through phenomenal kineses. Hence in ordinary speech we separate the kinetic cow from its metakinetic symbols in consciousness (the convex from the concave aspect), and call the former the cow itself, and the latter our idea of the cow. But, as before maintained, my idea of an object is for me the object. And this is now justified by our deeper analysis.

The physiologist, dealing with organic phenomena in terms of motion (kinesis), proclaims that the physical series is complete, that there is no necessity for the introduction of feeling which is at best but a by-product. The idealist, dealing with the processes of thought and emotion in terms of consciousness, proclaims that his series is complete—an external material universe is an unnecessary encumbrance. Each proclaims a half-truth; each sees that half of the truth which alone is visible from his special standpoint. Monism combines the two (and is, of course, scouted by both). It sees not only that the one series does not in any case interfere with the other, but that the conception of such an interference involves an impossibility and incongruity. As soon could one speak of the convexities of one side of a curved surface interfering with the corresponding concavities of the other side, as of the metakinetic series interfering with the kinetic series, which is its other aspect. But if the one cannot interfere with the other, neither can the one exist without the other. To apply the same analogy, as well might one speak of the convexities of a curved surface existing without the concavities of its other side, as of the kinetic phenomena of organic life as being conceivably the same in the absence of conscious intelligence.

Remembering, then, that just as the environment of kinetic phenomena is itself kinetic, with which consciousness can in no wise interfere, so is the environment of metakinetic phenomena, perception, thought, and emotion, itself metakinetic. Let us now proceed to consider some of the implications.

We have already seen that, in what we may regard as the earlier phases of organic and mental life, the series between stimulus and activity is a simple one, which may be kinetically represented thus—

Stimulus ? neural processes ? motor-activities;

but that when inhibition is developed, there arises an alternative, thus—

Stimulus? motor-activities.
northeast arrow
northeast arrow
inhibition thereof.

And we further saw that, as a result of this inhibition, the entering stimuli, instead of, as it were, rapidly running out of the organism in motor-activities, set up a more and more complex series of diffused and reverberating neural processes in the brain or other central ganglia.

From the metakinetic view-point these diffused and reverberating neural processes in the brain culminate in consciousness as thought, Æsthetic emotion, and the higher conceptual mental activities. Deeply as these influence conduct, they are, to a large extent, independent of conduct. A man's thoughts and Æsthetic yearnings may be of the truest and purest; but in the moment of temptation and action, when stimuli crowding in run through rapidly to action, he falls away. His conduct belies his ideals. Nevertheless, the ideals were there, but too far away in the region of thought and abstract Æsthetics to be operative in action.

Now, we may divide the metakinetic concomitants of neural processes into two categories: first, those which are intimately associated with neural processes directly leading to motor-activities; secondly, those which are, so to speak, floated off from these into the region of thought and Æsthetic emotion, and which are therefore associated with neural processes only indirectly or remotely leading to motor-activities. Both have, of course, kinetic equivalents in neural processes, but the former are directly associated with activities and conduct, and the latter are not.

Let me exemplify. Interpretations of nature, theories, hypotheses, belong to the latter class. Their association with activities is in the main indirect. Whether we believe in materialism, idealism, or monism, our conduct is much the same. People got out of the way of falling stones, and guarded against being caught by the incoming tide, before science comprised both phenomena under the theory of gravitation. The conduct of human-folk was not much altered by the replacement of the geocentric by a heliocentric explanation of the solar system. It matters not much how a man explains the lightning's flash so long as he avoids being struck. The bird continues to soar quite irrespective of man's prolonged discussion of how it can be explained on mechanical principles. And in general the practical activities of mankind remain much the same (I do not say quite the same, for there are remote and indirect results of the greatest importance in the long run) whatever their particular theory of the universe may be.

Now, let us note the implication. We have said a good deal in earlier chapters about natural elimination and selection. To which category of neural kineses do they apply—to those associated with practical results; or to those associated with theoretical results (supposing these to obtain below the level of man); or to both? Clearly to those associated with practical results. It matters not what theories a lion, or an adder, or a spider hold (supposing, again, that they are capable of theorizing, which I doubt). Its practical activities determine whether it survives or not. So, too, with men, so far as they are subject to natural elimination. It matters not what may be the nature of their thoughts, their Æsthetic yearnings, their ideals. According to their practical conduct, they are eliminated or escape elimination. In other words, elimination or natural selection applies only remotely or indirectly to the human race regarded as theorists, Æsthetes, or interpreters of nature.

Before proceeding to indicate to what laws our theories and interpretations of nature and moral ideals are subject, we may note that there are sundry activities of man, the outcome of his conceptual thought and emotion, which are also, under the conditions of social life, to a large extent beyond the pale of elimination. I refer to the Æsthetic activities—music, painting, sculpture, and the like; in a word, the activities associated with art, literature, and pure science. These, in the main, take rank alongside the ideas of which they are the outward expression. Natural selection, which deals with practical, life-preserving, and life-continuing activities, has little to say to them. They are neutral variations which, so far as elimination is concerned, are neither advantageous nor disadvantageous, and, therefore, remain unmolested.

We may, therefore, fully agree with Mr. Wallace, when he says,[KK] "We conclude, then, that the present gigantic development of the mathematical faculty [as also of the musical and artistic faculties] is wholly unexplained by the theory of natural selection, and must be due to some altogether distinct cause." Nay, we may go further, and say that it is only by misunderstanding the range of natural selection as an eliminator that any one could suppose that these faculties could be explained by that theory.

We must admit, then, that there are certain neural kineses which, from the fact that they are unassociated with life-preserving and life-continuing activities, are not subject to the law of elimination; and in the development of which natural selection cannot have been an essential factor. These, in their metakinetic aspect, are conceptual thoughts, emotions, and ideas. Remembering the distinction drawn in the chapter on "Organic Evolution" between origin and guidance, let us proceed to inquire, first, how these ideas have been guided to their present development; and, secondly, how we may suppose these special variations to have originated.

To understand their development, we must understand their environment. The environment of metakineses is, as we have already seen, constituted by other metakineses. What we have now to note is that the environment of conceptual ideas, as such, is constituted by other ideas. The immediate environment of an hypothesis is other hypotheses; of a moral ideal, other moral ideals; of an Æsthetic thought, other Æsthetic thoughts; of a religious conception, other religious conceptions. But not only are ideas environed by ideas of their own order; they are environed by ideas of other orders. Thus a scientific hypothesis or a moral ideal may be in harmony or conflict with religious conceptions, and its fate may be thereby determined; or a religious conception may be in harmony or conflict with psychological principles, and its acceptance or rejection thereby determined. So that we may say, in general, that the environment of an idea is the system of ideas among which it is introduced.

Of course, it must be clearly understood that it is with the individual mind that we are dealing. The scientific ideas, moral ideals, Æsthetic standards, religious conceptions, of a tribe, nation, or other community, are simply representative, either of the general views of the majority of the individuals, or more frequently of a majority among a cultivated minority. In any case, we have seen that metakineses are and must be an individual matter. For each individual there is a separate ideal world.

Through certain activities, notably language spoken or written, men can symbolize to each other the ideas that are taking metakinetic shape in their own minds. All-important, however, as is this power of intercommunication by means of language, it does not a whit alter the fact that the idea and its environment have to work out their relations to each other separately in each individual mind. My neighbour may symbolize, through language, his ideas in such a form that similar ideas may be called up in my mind; but it is there that they have to make good their claim for acceptance in the environment of the system of ideas among which they are introduced.

Now, what is the guiding principle of the evolution and development of ideas in the world of their metakinetic environment? Is there any principle analogous to that of elimination which we have seen to be of such high importance in organic evolution? I believe that there is. An idea is accepted or rejected according to its congruity or incongruity with the system of ideas among which it is introduced. The process has, perhaps, closer analogy with elimination than with selection, inasmuch as it would seem to proceed by the rejection of the incongruous, leaving both the congruous and the neutral. An idea or hypothesis may be accepted, at any rate provisionally, so long as it is not in contradiction to the theories and beliefs already existing in the mind.

It may, however, be objected that this view is at variance with the familiar observation that there are many excellent people who hold and maintain theories which are exceedingly incongruous, which seem, indeed, to us mutually antagonistic. Yes, to us. Brought into the environment of our system of ideas, one or other of these antagonistic views would be eliminated through incongruity. Not so, however, with those who hold both. Amid the environment of a less logical and less coherent system of ideas, both can find admission, if not as congruous, still as neutral. A sense of their incongruity is not aroused.

But there are some people, it may be said, who consciously hold views which they admit to be incongruous; who base all their scientific reasonings on a continuity of causation, but who, nevertheless, believe in miraculous interruptions of that continuity. In this case, however, the incongruity is made congruous in a higher synthesis. They belie themselves when they suppose that they are holding incongruous views. Stated at length, what they admit is that miraculous interventions are incongruous, not for them, but for those whose whole system of thought is cast in another mould than theirs—for the materialist and the infidel.

I cannot discuss the matter further here. This is not the place to show, or attempt to show, how the evolution of systems of thought has caused, or is causing, certain ideas, such as that of slavery, religious persecution, the moral and physical degradation of our poor, to reach that degree of incongruity which we signify as abhorrent; or how that evolution has caused yet more primitive ideas to seem positively repulsive. Nor is it the place to show, or attempt to show, how the advance of scientific knowledge has been constantly accompanied by the elimination of incongruous conceptions. I must content myself with the brief indication I have given of the principle of elimination through incongruity as applied to ideas.

It may be said that such a principle does not account for the origin of the new congruous ideas, but only for the getting rid of old incongruous ideas. Quite true. But I have grievously failed in my exposition of natural selection through elimination if I have not made it evident that this objection (if that can be called an objection which, in truth, is none) lies also at the door of Darwin's generalization.[KL] Now, from all that has been said in this chapter, it will be seen that, on the hypothesis of monism, we cannot regard organic and mental evolution as continuous the one into the other, but rather as parallel the one with the other—as the kinetic and metakinetic manifestations of the same process. Organic evolution is a matter of structure and activity. If the structure or the activity be not attuned to the environing conditions, it will be eliminated, those sufficiently well attuned surviving. Turning to the metakinetic aspect, we have seen that there are certain mental processes which are directly and closely associated with activities. Their evolution will be intimately associated with organic evolution. For if these processes lead to ill-attuned activities, the organism will be eliminated; and thus the evolution of well-attuned activities and their corresponding mental states will proceed side by side. We may, therefore, say, not incorrectly, that these lower phases of mental evolution are subject to the law of natural selection.

But when the neural processes which intervene between stimulus and activity become more complex and more roundabout; when, instead of being directly and closely associated with life-preserving activities, they are associated indirectly and remotely;—then they become, step by step, removed from their subjection to natural selection. And when, in man, the metakineses associated with these neural kineses assume the form of hypotheses, theories, interpretations of nature, moral ideals, and religious conceptions, these are, except in so far as they lead to activities which may conduce to elimination, no longer subject to the law of natural selection, unless we use this term in a somewhat metaphorical, or at least extended, sense. They are subject, as we have seen, to a new process of elimination through incongruity.

Similarly with that wide range of conduct in man which is the outcome of his conceptual life, and is removed from those merely life-preserving activities which are still, to some extent, under the influence of natural elimination. Conduct is here modified in accordance with the conceptual system of which it is the outcome and outward expression. And this higher conduct is subject, not to elimination through natural selection, but to elimination through incongruity. Slavery would never have been abolished through natural selection; by this means the modest behaviour of a chaste woman could not have been developed. To natural selection neither the Factory Acts nor the artistic products in this year's Academy were due; by this process were determined neither the conduct of John Howard nor that of Florence Nightingale. Some evolutionists have done no little injury to the cause they have at heart by vainly attempting to defend the untenable position that natural selection has been a prime factor in the higher phases of human conduct. I believe that natural selection has had little or nothing to do with them as such. They are the outcome of conceptual ideas, and are subject to the same process of elimination through incongruity.

So soon as, in the course of mental evolution, the idea of slavery became incongruous, and in certain minds abhorrent and repulsive, steps were taken to check the conduct which was the outward expression of this idea. So, too, in other cases. The reformer must not, however, be too far in advance of his generation, if his reform is to be practically carried out. When his ideas are so "advanced" as to be incongruous with those of all but a very small minority of his contemporaries, even they are forced to confess that the nation is not yet ripe for the changes they contemplate.

No one will question that artistic products are the outcome of artistic ideas. In the slow and difficult progress of a new school of painting or of music, we see exemplified the rejection of the new ideas through their incongruity with the old-fashioned artistic systems. Only gradually do there grow up new generations for whom these new ideas are not incongruous. For them the old-fashioned systems become incongruous; and if the school becomes dominant, artistic products embodying the old ideas are eliminated through incongruity. We are not all alike. Our mental systems are different. One artist will introduce into his canvas effects which, to the eye of another, will at once strike a jarring note of incongruity. To some minds the institution of slavery presents no incongruity. There are not wanting men for whom the degrading moral and physical conditions under which many of our poor are forced to live and work present little or no incongruity. To the Russian, English fidelity to the marriage vow is said to be as incongruous as, to an English woman, is the harem of an Eastern potentate.

In the higher phases of human conduct, then, the activities are subject to the law of the ideas of which they are the outcome—the law of elimination through incongruity.

I have said that natural selection has little or nothing to do with these higher phases of conduct. But has not human selection through preferential mating? I believe that it has; and I trust that it will have a still greater influence in the future. It is one of the noblest privileges of woman, for with her mainly lies the choice, that she may aid in raising humanity to a higher level. If once the idea of marrying for anything but pure affection could become utterly incongruous to woman's mental nature; and if once the idea of perpetuating any form of moral, intellectual, or physical deformity could become equally incongruous; the bettering of humanity, through the exclusion of the deformed in body and mind from any share in its continuance must inevitably follow. Here, again, ideas would determine conduct.

And what, we may now proceed to ask, is the physiological or kinetic aspect of this metakinetic process? The answer to this question involves the conception of what I would term "interneural evolution." Just as the environment of a conceptual idea is constituted by other conceptual ideas, so is the environment of its neural concomitant constituted by the other neural processes in the brain. Just as no idea can get itself accepted if it be in incongruity with the system of ideas among which it is introduced, so, too, can no neural process become established if it be not in harmony with the other neural processes of the cerebral hemispheres. The brain is a microcosm; its neural processes are interrelated; and the environment of any neural process is constituted by other neural processes.

A little consideration will show that this must be so; that it is only the physical or kinetic aspect of what is freely admitted when the mental or metakinetic aspect is under consideration. If it be admitted that states of consciousness are determined by other states of consciousness, and that states of consciousness are the concomitants of certain neural processes in the brain, it follows as a logical necessity that brain-neuroses, however originating, are determined in their evolution by other brain-neuroses; and that there has been a brain or interneural evolution, distinct from and yet intimately associated with the evolution of other bodily structures and activities. The more closely and directly brain-neuroses are associated with immediate activities, the more closely implicated is interneural evolution in the process of organic elimination through natural selection. But when long trains of neuroses take place in only remote and distant connection with other bodily activities, they are removed from the process of elimination through natural selection, and interneural evolution is allowed to proceed comparatively untrammelled.

I have already indicated my belief that abstraction (isolation), analysis, and conceptual ideas have been rendered possible through language, and are excellences unto which the lower animals do not attain. Hence I regard this comparatively untrammelled phase of interneural evolution as something essentially human, something which differentiates man from brute. And I would correlate man's greatly developed brain—inexplicable, I think, by natural selection alone—with this later and special phase of interneural evolution. Even in the lowest savage this brain-evolution has proceeded a long way. I am not fitted in this matter to offer an opinion which would carry much weight. But from all that I have read I gather that savages have in all cases elaborated a complex—often a highly complex—interpretation of nature and theory of things. The interpretation may seem bizarre and incongruous enough to us, full of fetishism and strange superstitions, but it is an interpretation; to the savage it presents no incongruity; to him the incongruity is in the oddly assorted beliefs of the missionary. His system of ideas is, in fact, one of the many possible systems to which mental evolution may give rise.

For what we call systems of thoughts, interpretations of nature, theories of things, are so many genera and species which have resulted from this later phase of metakinetic evolution. Our methods are at present too coarse, our powers too limited, to enable us to determine these species from their kinetic aspect. The brains of Kaffir and Boer, of ploughboy and merchant, of materialist and idealist, are too subtly wrought to enable us to trace the systems of kineses which were the concomitants of their scheme of beliefs. But we can learn something of the genera and species from their metakinetic aspect as symbolized through language and other bodily activities. They fall into certain groups, fetishistic, spiritualistic, materialistic, idealistic, monistic, and so on, and within these groups there are sub-divisions. This is not the place to consider them or discuss their characteristics. What I wish to note about them is that, diverse as they seem and are, each is a coherent product of mental evolution. In each, all that is incongruous to itself has been or is being eliminated.

There are some people, however, who are surprised at the incongruity of interpretations of nature among each other. Fetishism, they say, has been proved to be utterly false. It constitutes a hideous and grotesque delirium. How can that which is utterly and completely false to nature have had a natural evolution? Now, for the Élite of the Aryan race, whose systems of ideas have been moulded in accordance with the conceptions of modern science, no doubt the fetishism of the poor savage seems sufficiently incongruous and grotesque. So, too, does the system of ideas of the Right Rev. Bishop of —— appear no doubt, to the learned and eminent Professor ——, and vice versÂ. And so, too, no doubt, does the system of ideas of the white man (who introduces firearms and firewater, and preaches the gospel of forgiveness and temperance) appear to the poor savage. Each in his degree wonders how this falsity, this incongruity, can have had a natural genesis. But in each case the falsity and the incongruity is not within the system itself, but between different systems.

Once more, I repeat that if the individual nature of the systems of ideas be not adequately grasped, the nature of mental evolution will not be apprehended. States of consciousness can only be determined by other states of consciousness; and states of consciousness are for the individual subject, and for him alone. Conceptual ideas are states of consciousness; and "falsity to nature" means, and can only mean, incongruity with the environing states of consciousness in the individual mind. For the savage there is no falsity to nature in his fetishism. The idea presents no incongruity with his system of ideas; no more incongruity than filed teeth, flattened head, or pierced nose do to his standard of beauty. It is with our system of ideas (i.e. mine or yours) that his fetishism is false and incongruous. The falsity or incongruity, I repeat, is not within the system itself, but between different systems.

It may still, however, be said—Only one interpretation of nature can be true; all others must be false. And the falsity is not merely incongruity with other ideas in other systems of thought or belief; it is falsity to the plain and obvious facts of nature.

We may freely admit that only one interpretation of nature can be true. But who is to determine which? Who can decide the question between monist and materialist? Who dare arbitrate between the bishop and the professor? The criterion of fitness in this case, as in others, is survival; and who can say what existing interpretation of nature (if any) shall outlive all its competitors? Who can say what will be the nature of the further evolution of any existing philosophical creed? The elimination of the false is a slow and gradual process; and many degenerate systems of ideas may linger on in the darker corners of the world of men. False or out of harmony as they seem to be with the higher phases of development; false or out of harmony as they would be with a different and more exalted environment; they are not false or out of harmony with the environment in the midst of which we find them; they are not false or out of harmony with "the plain and obvious facts of nature," as these exist for the ill-developed or savage mind.

The plain and obvious facts of nature, as interpreted by men of science in 1890, have simply no existence for the untutored or the savage intellect. For him they have not emerged into the light of consciousness. But while we cannot blame the savage for entertaining ideas which are false to facts which for him have no existence, we may none the less believe that his system of ideas is not among those which are destined to become predominant species. So far as we can judge, the winning species among systems of ideas and interpretations of nature are those in which the greatest number of ideas are fused into harmonious synthesis; in which all the ideas are congruous, few or none neutral; and in which the abstract or conceptual ideas, when brought into contact with concrete or perceptual states of consciousness, are found to be in harmony and congruity therewith.

There is one more question in this connection on which I must say a few words. How, it may be asked, has the world become peopled, for many primitive and savage folk, with a crowd of immaterial spiritual essences, so that it is scarcely too much to say that, for some of these peoples, everything has its double; and there is no material existence that has not its spiritual counterpart?

I would connect this almost universal tendency with the origin of abstract ideas (isolates) through language. When the named predominant gave rise to the isolate (see p.374), it could scarcely fail that the primitive speakers and thinkers should tend to regard those qualities or properties which they could isolate in thought (conceptually) as also isolable in fact (perceptually). And we may well suppose, though this is, of course, hypothetical, that one of the earliest severances to be thus effected through isolation was the severance of mind and body. The first phenomena that the nascent reason would endeavour to explain would probably be those of daily life and almost hourly experience. Many familiar facts would seem to point to the temporary or permanent divorce of the part which is conscious and feels, from the part which is tangible and visible. During wakeful life the two are closely associated. The visible part, or body, is conscious. But during sleep, or under the influence of a heavy blow, the visible part, which before was conscious, is conscious no longer. The conscious part is, therefore, absent, but returns again after a while. On death the conscious part returns no more. The divorce of the two has become permanent.

And then comes in the confirmatory testimony of dreams. In dreams the savage has seen his enemy, though that enemy's body was far away. Here, then, is the spirit which has left the body during sleep. In dreams also the slain enemy or the dead chief appears. The spirit, permanently divorced from the body, still walks the earth in spirit-guise.

Many occurrences would seem like the fulfilled threats of dead enemies or the fulfilled promises of dead ancestors. How can these be explained? Are they not produced by the ghost of the departed enemy, by the spirit of the deceased ancestor? And if these spirits are still powerful to act, why not petition them to act in certain ways?

Probably primitive man would explain all activities anthropomorphically. What knows he of gravitation or the laws of the winds? He knows himself as agent, and attributes his activities to the immaterial spirit within him; for when this is absent during sleep or in death these activities cease. All acting things might, therefore, come to be regarded as dual in their nature—possessed of a sensible material bodily part, and an insensible active spiritual part. And thus the whole world might be peopled with living existences of the spiritual order.

Now, whether the fetishistic faith arose in some such way as this or not—and we can never know how it arose, but can only guess—there would be nothing in such primitive explanations which would violate the law of congruity. They would have, therefore, a perfectly natural genesis. The attempted interpolation at such a stage of primitive reason of any modern scientific conception would be futile. It would at once be rejected through incongruity.

The history of scientific conceptions seems to show that they were first adopted with regard to phenomena on the very horizon of thought—in regions, that is to say, most remote from the central citadel of the soul. Only gradually have they, little by little, encroached upon this centre; and the application of them to physiology and psychology is a matter of quite modern times. Even to-day only a minority, but an increasing minority, of thinkers are prepared indissolubly to unite the mind and body, so long divorced in thought, so completely united, as many of us believe, in their essential being.

I have now, I trust, illustrated at sufficient length the principle of elimination through incongruity in interneural and its associated metakinetic or mental evolution. This, however, like natural selection, is a matter of guidance; we have still to consider the question of origin.

In truth, we know too little on the subject to enable us to discuss it with much profit. From the kinetic or organic point of view, neural variations take their place among the other variations, the origin of which, as we have already found, is so hard to account for. There may be a tendency for neural vibrations to mutually influence each other (like two clocks placed side by side), and thus gradually to drag each other into one harmonious and congruous rhythm. But this, though not improbable, is purely hypothetical. There is the hypothesis of the inheritance of acquired variations, the increased congruity acquired by the parent being in some degree transmitted to the offspring. There is the view which Mr. Wallace adopts[KM] with regard to the origin of accessory plumes, that such variations may be due to "a surplus of strength, vitality, and growth-power, which is able to expend itself in this way without injury," and not without profit. The development of the social habit, the mutual aid and protection thus afforded, may well have left a balance of the life-energy, previously employed in individual self-preservation, available for this purpose. And then there is always the hypothesis of favourable fortuitous variations to fall back upon.

On only one of these points do I propose to say a few words—that of the possible inheritance of acquired variations.

Let us restate the problem here for the sake of clearness. There is, according to the suggestion put forward in this chapter, an interneural evolution, leading to an harmonious development of the neuroses in the individual brain. But this special evolution of the brain is nowise independent of the more general evolution of the body. The human being, as an organism, is still subject to natural elimination and human selection. Elimination through the action of surrounding physical conditions, although it has played some part in the evolution of man, is not a factor of the first importance. Elimination through enemies is more important, but has not much bearing on the question at present before us—the evolution of the conceptual. Elimination by competition, again, though a factor of yet greater importance in human evolution, has, nevertheless, so far as individuals are concerned, but little bearing on our present question. Few are eliminated through the absence of the conceptual faculty. Natural elimination, then, is, as Mr. Wallace well pointed out, practically excluded in this matter. No doubt, in the struggle between tribes and nations, that community is most likely to be successful in which there is rational guidance. No doubt, during the earlier phases of the development of man on our islands, the elimination of the irrational was a factor in progress. But if we take the last three centuries of English history, I doubt whether it can be shown that there has been much elimination determined by the relative absence of conceptual ideas and emotions.

Human selection has been a much more important factor. Those individuals which showed the higher types of intellectual thought have been constantly selected. Riches, rank, and social position have been bestowed upon them. Of course, there have been exceptions; great intellects have been allowed to languish in their lifetime, and have only obtained recognition through their works after death. But every day there is less chance of a genius dying in a garret. And the best intellects, being thus selected and chosen out from among their fellow-men, form to some extent a distinct social class. Segregation is thus effected; and intermarriage takes place within this intellectual caste, with the result that the conditions are eminently favourable for the inheritance of intellectual qualities.

Now, is this process of selection of the intellectual, this segregation into a caste, and the inheritance of innate intellectual qualities sufficient to account for the facts of intellectual progress; or must we call in to our aid the inheritance of individual increments? I confess I cannot say. Direct and satisfactory evidence, one way or the other, is almost impossible to obtain.

Must we, then, leave the question undecided? I think we must so far as direct evidence is concerned. I may have a general belief that there has been some transmission of acquired increment of intellectual faculty. But unless I can substantiate it by definite facts, I cannot expect to convince any one who holds the opposite view. And definite facts of sufficient cogency I am unable to adduce. It is practically impossible to exclude the influence of human selection; and unless we can do this the followers of Dr. Weismann will not be satisfied.

Still, general belief—which means the net result of one's consideration of the subject—counts for something. We must remember the question is one of origin, and not of guidance. The guidance of human selection is unquestioned and unquestionable. But when we consider the intellectual progress of the last three centuries, and ask whether all this has originated in fortuitous brain-variations, which human selection has simply picked out from the total mass of available material, an affirmative answer seems to me a little difficult of acceptance. There seems to have been a definite tendency to vary in this particular direction, a general raising of the intellectual level, which is difficult to account for unless it be due to the persistent employment of the intellectual faculties.

To put the matter in another way. I do not think that, during the last three centuries, there has been a large amount of elimination of the unintellectual. Such elimination as there has been of this nature has probably been more than compensated by the slower rate of multiplication of the intellectual classes. Elimination, then, in this matter may be practically disregarded. But it is obvious that selection, without the removal or exclusion of the non-selected, does nothing to alter the general level[KN] with regard to the particular quality or faculty concerned. It is merely a classification of the individuals in order of merit in this particular respect. It is, in a word, a segregation-factor. It arranges the individuals in classes, but it does not alter the position of the mean around which they vary.

Let me explain by means of an analogous case. Fifty boys, who have been admitted to a public school, await examination in a class-room. They are at present unclassified, but there is a mean of ability among the whole fifty. A week afterwards they are distributed in different forms. Some are selected for a higher form, others have to take a lower place. But though selection has classified the material, it has not altered the position of the mean of ability among the fifty boys. This can only be done by expelling a certain number or excluding them from the school.

Granted, therefore, that elimination is practically excluded, human selection can at most classify the individuals according to their intellectual faculties. It cannot raise the mean standard of intellectuality. If, therefore, this mean standard has been raised during the last three centuries, there has been a tendency to vary in this particular direction, which may,[KO] to say the least of it, be due to the inheritance of individual increment.

I am, of course, aware that the matter is complicated by the increased and increasing diffusion of knowledge through the printing-press and by the extension and improvement of education. But education, to take that first, though it may raise the level of each generation, can have no cumulative effect. For the effects of education cannot, on Professor Weismann's hypothesis, be inherited. You may educate brain and muscle in the individual, but his heir will inherit no good or ill effects therefrom. Each generation goes back and starts from the old level. There is no summation of effect; or, if there is, it tells so far against Professor Weismann.

And with regard to the diffusion of knowledge, this, though it brings more grist to the intellectual mill, can have no effect in raising the mean standard of excellence in the mill itself. There is more to grind; but this does not improve the grinding apparatus; or, if it does, it tells so far against Professor Weismann's hypothesis. To vary the analogy, the diffusion of knowledge increases the store of available food; but it does not bring with it any additional power of digesting the food; or, if it does, it may be through inherited increments of mean digestive power. It may, however, be maintained that there is no conclusive proof that the mean intellectual level of Englishmen to-day is any higher than it was in the days of the Tudors. If so, of course, my argument falls to the ground. I have no desire to dogmatize on the subject. I merely set down the reasons, such as they are, and for what they are worth, which lead me to entertain a general belief that the intellectual progress of Englishmen during the past three hundred years has been in part due to the inheritance of individually acquired faculty.


Mental evolution, then, is the metakinetic equivalent of interneural, or, in us vertebrates, brain-evolution. The brain forms a kinetic system in some sense independent of, and yet in constant touch with, the kinetic system of the world around. Its kineses, though they do not resemble, yet more or less accurately represent or symbolize, the kineses of the surrounding universe. As the kineses of the world around are interdependent and harmonious, so are the neural kineses of the brain interdependent and harmonious. And no modification of this kinesis which is out of harmony with the kinetic system already established in the brain can be incorporated with that existing system. Such attempted modification is eliminated through incongruity.

Associated with this brain-kinesis, and forming its inner aspect, is a metakinetic system in which the higher manifestations rise to the level of full consciousness; others form sub-conscious states; others are unconscious. But the whole form a coherent system answering to the coherent kinetic system.

Consciousness is thus associated only with the phenomena of that kinetic microcosm which we call the brain (or other interneural system). Obviously, therefore, it does not and cannot deal directly with anything outside the brain. Its knowledge is solely and entirely a knowledge of the representative occurrences of the interneural system. But out of these occurrences a surrounding world of phenomena is constructed in mental symbolism.

The brain itself, however, is part of the world of phenomena thus constructed in mental symbolism; and the world, therefore, dissolves in pure idealism, leaving only a fleeting series of states of consciousness, if we do not assume the existence of a system of "things in themselves" (noumena), of which kineses and metakineses are the phenomenal manifestations. Whether the "things in themselves" in any sense resemble their phenomenal manifestations, we cannot say. It is as difficult philosophically to conceive that they can as it is practically to conceive that they do not. And since, whether they do or do not, the world we live in is phenomenal; since it is to phenomena that we have to adapt our conduct; since it is with phenomena that all our thoughts and emotions have reference; since the world we construct in mental symbolism is the world in which we live and move and have our being; it is not only convenient, but logically justifiable, to call this world of phenomena the really existing world for us human-folk and other sentient organisms.

As in the kinetic interneural system, or brain, so, too, in the metakinetic system, no modification of the metakinesis which is out of harmony with the existing metakinesis can be incorporated therewith. Such attempted modification is eliminated through incongruity.

In the lower stages of mental evolution, those which belong to the perceptual sphere, where the neuroses are closely connected with the life-preserving activities of the organism, the survival or non-survival of the system of neuroses is largely dependent on the fitness of the associated activities to the conditions of life. But in the higher stages of mental evolution, those which belong to the conceptual sphere, the connection of certain brain-neuroses with life-preserving motor-activities becomes less close and direct. The corresponding ideas, thoughts, and emotions become floated off into a more abstract region. Here the system of ideas, as such, that is to say, so far as they are removed from life-preserving activities, is determined mainly by the law of congruity. But there are several such systems. There are, indeed, as many systems as there are minds; but these may be classified in several distinct groups, which we may liken to genera and species. These are the various interpretations of nature, theories of things, and the like; the systems of ideas, thoughts, conceptions, emotions, beliefs, which, as we say, belong to us, each and all, and which determine to which metakinetic species we belong. These are the highest products of mental evolution; and among them there is, so to speak, a struggle, if not for existence, at any rate for prevalence. Which shall eventually prevail—a spiritual interpretation of nature, a material interpretation, a monistic interpretation, or other, who shall say? But, so far as we can judge, the winning species among systems of ideas and interpretations of nature are likely to be those in which the greatest number of ideas are fused into harmonious synthesis; in which all the ideas are congruous; and in which the abstract or conceptual ideas, when brought into contact with concrete or perceptual states of consciousness, are found to be in harmony and congruity therewith.

NOTES

[A]An interesting problem concerning the atmosphere is suggested by certain geological facts. In our buried coal-seams and other carbonaceous deposits a great quantity of carbon, for the most part abstracted from the atmosphere, has been stored away. Still greater quantities of carbon are imprisoned in the substance of our limestones, which contain, when pure, 44 per cent. of this element. A large quantity of oxygen has also been taken from the atmosphere to combine with other elements during their oxidation. The question is—Was the atmosphere, in the geological past, more richly laden with carbonic acid gas, of which some has entered into combination with lime to form limestone, while some has been decomposed by plants, the carbon being buried as coal, and the oxygen as products of oxidation? Or, has the atmosphere been furnished with continuous fresh supplies of carbonic acid gas?

[B]It has before been noticed that the organs themselves have their periods of rest. The rhythm of rest and repose in the heart is not that of the activity and sleep of the organism, but that of the contraction and relaxation of the organ itself.

[C]From a popular article of the author's on "Horns and Antlers," in Atalanta.

[D]It will be well here to introduce the technical terms for these changes. The general term for chemical actions occurring in the tissues of a living creature is metabolism; where the change is of such a nature that complex and unstable compounds are built up and stored for a while, it is called anabolism; where complex unstable compounds break up into less complex and relatively stable compounds, the term katabolism is applied. We shall speak of anabolic changes as constructive; katabolic, as disruptive, or sometimes, explosive.

[E]I do not mean, of course, to imply that there is no reconstruction during activity, but that it is then distinctly outbalanced by disruptive changes.

[F]Professor Geddes and Mr. J. Arthur Thomson, in their interesting work on "The Evolution of Sex," regard the ovum in especial, and the female in general, as preponderatingly anabolic (see note, p.32); while the sperm in especial, and the male in general, are on their view preponderatingly katabolic. Regarding, as I do, the food-yolk as a katabolic product, I cannot altogether follow them. The differentiation seems to me to have taken place along divergent lines of katabolism. In the ovum, katabolism has given rise to storage products; in the sperm, to motor activities associated with a tendency to fission. The contrast is not between anabolic and katabolic tendencies, but between storage katabolism and motor katabolism. Nor do I think that "the essentially katabolic male-cell brings to the ovum a supply of characteristic waste products, or katastates, which stimulate the latter to division" (l.c., p.162). I believe that it brings an inherited tendency to fission, and thus reintroduces into the fertilized ovum the tendency which, as ovum, it had renounced in favour of storage katabolism.

[G]On the other hand, three ova of the crustacean Apus are said to coalesce to form the single ovum from which one embryo develops.

[H]"The Evolution of Sex," p.84.

[I]In some forms of life the opening of the cup marks the position of the future mouth: in others, of the future vent. In yet others it elongates into a slit, occupying the whole length of the embryo; the middle part of the slit closes up, and the opening at the far ends mark the position, the one of the future mouth, the other of the future vent.

[J]In technical language, the outer layer of cells is called the epiblast, the inner layer the hypoblast, and the mid-layer between them the mesoblast.

[K]In technical language, the opening by which the primitive digestive cavity (or mesenteron) communicates with the exterior is called the blastopore. When this closes, the new opening for the mouth is called the stomodoeum; that for the vent, the proctodoeum.

[L]We have seen that when volume tends to outrun surface, fission may take place, whereby the same volume has increased surface. But in unfavourable nutritive conditions, the same surface which had before been sufficient for nutrition may become, under the less favourable circumstances, insufficient, and fission may again take place to give a larger absorbent surface. Hence, possibly, the connection between insufficient nutriment and highly subdivided sperms.

[M]Samuel Butler in England, and Ewald Hering in Prague, have ingeniously likened this hereditary persistence to "organic memory." What are ordinarily called memory, habit, instinct, and embryonic reconstruction, are all referable to the memory of organic matter. The analogy, if used with due caution, is a helpful one, what we call memory being the psychical aspect (under certain special organic and neural conditions) of what under the physical aspect we call persistence.

[N]I have also to thank Mr. Edward Wilson for kindly giving me the measurements of three or four bats in the Bristol Museum.

[O]A millimetre is about 1/25 of an inch, or more exactly .03937 inch.

[P]In nearly all cases the measurements were checked by comparing the two wings. In one or two instances there were differences of as much as two or three millimetres between the bones of the two sides of the body, but in most cases they exactly corresponded.

[Q]We are anxious to extend our observations and to compare series of bats from different localities. If any of my readers should feel disposed to help us, by sending specimens (with the locality duly indicated) to Mr. H. Charbonnier, 7, The Triangle South, Clifton, Bristol, we shall be grateful.

[R]Nature, vol. xli. p. 393. The variation in molluscs is often considerable. In one of the bays in the basement hall of the Natural History Museum is a series showing the variation in size, form, and sculpturing of Paludomus loricatus, which is found in the streams of Ceylon. These varieties have in former times been named as ten distinct species!

[S]More observations and fuller knowledge on this latter point and on the relative numbers of the sexes in different species are much to be desired. It is clear that the number of offspring mainly depends upon the number of females. But if it be true that good times and favourable conditions lead to an increased production of females, while hard times and unfavourable conditions lead to a relative increase of males, then it is evident that good times will lead to a more rapid increase and hard times to a less rapid increase of the species. Suppose, for example, in a particular district food and other conditions were especially favourable for frogs. Among the well-nourished tadpoles there would be a preponderance of females. In the next generation the many females would produce abundant offspring (for one male may fertilize the ova laid by several females). There would be a greater number of tadpoles to compete for the same amount of nutriment. They would be less nourished. There would be less females; and in the succeeding generation a diminished number of tadpoles. Thus to some extent a balance between the number of tadpoles and the amount of available nutrition would be maintained. These conclusions are, perhaps, too theoretical to be of much value, while the tendency here indicated would be but one factor among many.

[T]"Origin of Species," pp. 62, 63.

[U]"Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 177.

[V]I may here draw attention to the fact that the bats whose wing-bone measurements were given above are those which have so far survived and escaped such elimination as is now in progress.

[W]"Origin of Species," p. 109.

[X]"Darwinism," p. 106.

[Y]Ibid. p. 106.

[Z]Proceedings Liverpool Biological Society, 1889.

[AA]Since this chapter was written, Mr. Poulton has published his interesting and valuable work on "The Colours of Animals," from which I have contrived to insert one or two additional examples.

[AB]Ann. and Mag. Nat. Hist., September, 1889, p. 209, quoted by Poulton, "Colours of Animals," p. 55.

[AC]Nature, vol. xxxv. p. 77.

[AD]Many other instances might be added. The hornet clear-wing moth (Sphecia apiformis) mimics the hornet or wasp; the narrow-bordered bee-hawk moth (Sesia bombyliformis) mimics a bumble-bee. These insects may be seen in the lepidoptera drawers in the Natural History Museum. But perhaps the most wonderful instance of insect-mimicry is that observed by Mr. W. L. Sclater, and given by Mr. E. B. Poulton, in his "Colours of Animals" (p. 252), where a (probably) homopterous insect mimics a leaf-cutting ant, together with its leafy burden—a membranous expansion in the mimic closely resembling the piece of leaf carried by the particular kind of ant he resembles.

[AE]The late Mr. H. W. Oakley first drew my attention to this snake. Since then Mr. Hammond Tooke has described the facts in Nature, vol. xxxiv. p. 547.

[AF]Nature, vol. xlii. p. 115.

[AG]Since the above was written and sent to press, there has been added, at the Natural History Museum, in the basement hall, a case illustrating the adaptation of external colouring to the conditions of life. All the animals, birds, etc., there grouped were collected in the Egyptian desert, whence also the rocks, stones, and sand on which they are placed were brought. Though somewhat crowded, they exemplify protective resemblance very well.

[AH]I have to thank Mr. H. A. Francis for drawing my attention to this, and showing me the insects in his cabinet.

[AI]"Colours of Animals," p. 73.

[AJ]"Origin of Species," p. 161.

[AK]"Descent of Man," summary of chap. xvi. pt. ii.

[AL]Ibid. chap. xiv.

[AM]"Darwinism," p. 108.

[AN]Its importance in artificial selection was emphasized by Darwin: "The prevention of free crossing, and the intentional matching of individual animals, are the corner-stones of the breeder's art" ("Animals and Plants under Domestication," ii. 62).

[AO]From the absence of interblending in some cases (to be considered shortly), both brown and green forms may be produced; and under certain circumstances, even a power of becoming either brown or green in the presence of appropriate stimuli.

[AP]Wallace, "Darwinism," p. 172, where other examples are cited.

[AQ]Ibid. pp. 217, et seq.

[AR]Journal of the LinnÆan Society, vol. xix. No. 115: "Zoology."

[AS]"Animals and Plants under Domestication," p. 145.

[AT]Ibid. chap. xvii.

[AU]"Darwinism," p. 326.

[AV]"Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 65. For Darwin's general conclusions on hybridism, see vol. ii. p. 162 of the same work.

[AW]"In every case there are two factors, namely, the nature of the organism and the nature of the conditions. The former seems to be much the more important; for nearly similar variations sometimes arise under, as far as we can judge dissimilar conditions; and, on the other hand, dissimilar variations arise under conditions which appear to be nearly uniform" ("Origin of Species," p. 6).

[AX]See "Evolution without Natural Selection," by Charles Dixon. This author's facts are valuable; his theories are ill digested.

[AY]Nature, vol. xlii. p. 136.

[AZ]We may here note, in passing, the fact that the changes of life-forms in a succession of beds points in nine cases out of ten rather to substitution through migration than to transmutation. Still, there are notable cases of transmutation, as in the fresh-water Planorbes of Steinhem, in Wittenberg (described, after Hilgendorf, by O. Schmidt, "The Doctrine of Descent," p. 96).

[BA]I would ask historians whether there have not been, in English history, good times of free and beneficial divergence exemplified in diverse intellectual activity, hard times of rigorous elimination, and intermediate times of placid, somewhat humdrum conservatism.

[BB]Two more technical examples may be noticed in a note. (1) Professor Haeckel has recently (Challenger Reports, vol. xxviii.) shown that the Siphonophora include two groups, closely resembling each other, but of different ancestry: (a) The DisconanthÆ, traceable to trachomedusoid ancestors; (b) the SiphonanthÆ, traceable to anthomedusoid ancestors like Sarsia. (2) M. Paul Pelseneer has been led to the conclusion that the pteropod molluscs also include two groups resembling each other, but of different ancestry: (a) The Thecosomes, traceable to tornatellid ancestors; (b) the Gymnosomes, traceable to aphysiid ancestors. In each case, the ancestral sea-slug has been modified for a free-swimming life.

[BC]For evidence in copious abundance, see Nicholson's "Manual of PalÆontology," new edition, vol. i.: "Vertebrata," by R. Lydekker.

[BD]"Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol ii. p. 239.

[BE]Or in certain "physiological units" (Herbert Spencer), or "plastidules" (Haeckel), which may be regarded as organic molecules exhibiting their special properties under vital conditions.

[BF]Nature, vol. xxxix. p. 486.

[BG]Darwin, "Animals and Plants under Domestication," 2nd edit., vol. ii. chap. xxvii., from which the following description and quotations are taken.

[BH]For an excellent account of the genesis and growth of the modern views of heredity, see Mr. J. Arthur Thomson's paper on "The History and Theory of Heredity:" Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh, 1889.

[BI]Geddes and Thomson, "The Evolution of Sex," p. 92.

[BJ]Weismann, "Essays on Heredity," English translation, p. 173.

[BK]Weismann, "Essays on Heredity," p. 205.

[BL]A few pages earlier (p. 200) in the same essay, Professor Weismann says, "A sudden transformation of the nucleo-plasm of a somatic cell into that of a germ-cell would be almost as incredible as the transformation of a mammal into an amoeba." This at first sight does not seem quite consistent with the subsequent sentence which I have quoted in the text; for here, at any rate, the daughters of "mammals" are said to be converted into "amoebÆ." But this is no doubt because the amoebÆ (germ-plasms) are contained in the mammals (body-cells). (See the quotations that follow in the text.)

[BM]Weismann, "Essays on Heredity," p. 207.

[BN]Weismann, "Essays on Heredity," p. 179.

[BO]It will, of course, be understood that a minute fragment of germ-plasm is capable of almost unlimited growth by assimilation of nutritive material, its properties remaining unchanged during such growth.

[BP]Latency is here neglected. Mr. Francis Galton has shown, statistically, that the offspring, among human folk, inherit 1/4 from each parent, 1/16 from each grandparent, and the remaining 1/4 from more remote ancestors. In domesticated animals, reversion to characters of distant ancestors sometimes occurs. This, however, does not invalidate the argument in the text, which is that sexual admixture tends towards the mean of the race (ancestors included), and cannot be credited with new and unusually favourable variations. The prepotency of one parent is also here neglected.

[BQ]See his valuable paper on "Divergent Evolution," Lin. Soc. Zool., No. cxx.

[BR]One parthenogenetic form—the drone—has been shown by Blochmann to extrude a second polar cell. This observation is in serious opposition to Dr. Weismann's theory.

[BS]Weismann, "Essays on Heredity," pp. 355, 378.

[BT]The law of compensation of growth or balancement was suggested at nearly the same time by Goethe and Geoffrey Saint-Hilaire. The application in the text has not, so far as I know, been before suggested.

[BU]Darwin spoke of changed conditions acting "directly on the organization or indirectly through the reproductive system." Now, since Professor Weismann has taught us to reconsider these questions, we speak of such conditions as acting directly on the germ or indirectly through the body. The germ is no longer subordinate to the body, but the body to the germ.

[BV]July 15, 1876. Since reprinted in "The Advancement of Science," p. 273.

[BW]Herbert Spencer, "Principles of Biology," vol. i. p. 256.

[BX]Mr. J. A. Thomson has published a most valuable "Synthetic Summary of the Influence of the Environment upon the Organism" (Proceedings Royal Physiological Society, Edinburgh: vol. ix. pt. 3, 1888). The case of the Amazonian parrots was communicated to Darwin by Mr. Wallace ("Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 269).

[BY]St. George Mivart, "On Truth," p. 378.

[BZ]Op. cit., p. 47. I venture to say, "with some assurance," because Charles Darwin, who had also considered this matter, writes, "Who will pretend to decide how far the thick fur of Arctic animals, or their white colour, is due to the direct action of a severe climate, and how far to the preservation of the best-protected individuals during a long succession of generations?" ("Animals and Plants under Domestication," p. 415).

[CA]"Organic Evolution," English translation, p. 88.

[CB]"Contributions to Natural Selection," p. 197.

[CC]Since this was written, Mr. Poulton has described his results in an interesting volume on "The Colours of Animals" (q.v.).

[CD]See Journal of Anatomy and Physiology, vol. xxii. p. 215.

[CE]See Professor Herdman's Inaugural Address, Liverpool Biological Society, 1888.

[CF]Francis Galton, "Inquiries into Human Faculty," p. 216.

[CG]That the epidermis is thicker on the palms of the hands and the soles of the feet in the infant long before birth, may be attributable to the inherited effects of use or pressure. It can hardly be held that the thickening of the skin in these parts is of elimination value.

[CH]The instances cited are from "Animals and Plants under Domestication."

[CI]It is beyond the scope of this book to give the evidences of evolution. Such evidence from embryology, from distribution, and from palÆontology, is now abundant. For palÆontological evidence, see Nicholson's "Manual of PalÆontology," 3rd edit., especially the second volume on "Vertebrates," by R. Lydekker.

[CJ]Weismann, "Essays on Heredity," p. 24.

[CK]Ibid. p. 140.

[CL]Weismann, "Essays on Heredity," p. 90.

[CM]Ibid. p. 292. See also a discussion in Nature, in which Mr. Romanes and Professor Ray Lankester took part, beginning vol. xli. p. 437.

[CN]Weismann, "Essay on Heredity," p. 140.

[CO]"Origin of Species," p. 110.

[CP]With regard to blind cave-fish, Professor Ray Lankester has suggested that some selection has been effected. Those animals whose sight-sensitiveness enabled them to detect a glimmer of light would escape to the exterior, leaving those with congenitally weak sight to remain and procreate in the darkness of the cave.

[CQ]Darwin, "Descent of Man," pt. ii. chap. viii.

[CR]"Darwinism," chap. x.

[CS]"Darwinism," p. 295. Messrs. Geddes and Thomson, "The Evolution of Sex," p. 28, also contend that "combative energy and sexual beauty rise pari passu with male katabolism."

[CT]"Darwinism," p. 293.

[CU]Mr. Poulton, who takes a similar line of argument in his "Colours of Animals," lays special stress upon the production of white (see p. 326).

[CV]See Chapter VIII.

[CW]"Darwinism," p. 172.

[CX]See "Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 80.

[CY]"Darwinism," p. 332.

[CZ]"The Colour-Sense," by Grant Allen, p. 95.

[DA]That on "The Emotions of Animals" (X.).

[DB]"Darwinism," p. 318.

[DC]Natural History Society of Wisconsin, vol. i. (1889).

[DD]"Darwinism," p. 286.

[DE]On the negative character of disuse, see p. 196.

[DF]Cope, "Origin of the Fittest," p. 374.

[DG]It would appear, from certain passages of his "Darwinism," that Mr. A. R. Wallace (e.g. p. 139, note) holds or held similar views. "The genera Ateles and Colobus," he says, "are two of the most purely arboreal types of monkeys, and it is not difficult to conceive that the constant use of the elongated fingers for climbing from tree to tree, and catching on to branches while making great leaps, might require all the nervous energy and muscular growth to be directed to the fingers, the small thumb remaining useless." I should also have quoted Mr. Wallace's account of the twisting round of the eyes of flat-fishes—where he says that the constant repetition of the effort of twisting the eye towards the upper side of the head, when the bony structure is still soft and flexible, causes the eye gradually to move round the head till it comes to the upper side—had he not subsequently disclaimed this explanation (see Nature, vol. xl. p. 619). It is possible that Mr. Wallace, notwithstanding the words "constant use" in the passage I have quoted, merely intends to imply that the elongated fingers are of advantage in climbing, and are thus subject to natural selection, the thumb diminishing through economy of growth.

[DH]I find, on rereading one of his articles, that I have here unwittingly adopted one of Mr. Romance's arguments (see Nature, vol. xxxvi. p. 406). The instance Mr. Romanes cites is the curious habit of dogs turning round before they lie down.

[DI]Mr. Darwin, while contending that the modifications need not all have been simultaneous, says, "Although natural selection would thus tend to give the male elk its present structure, yet it is probable that the inherited effects of use, and of the mutual action of part on part, have been equally or more important" ("Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 328).

[DJ]Midland Naturalist, November, 1889.

[DK]See ante, p. 52.

[DL]Nature, vol. xli. p. 511.

[DM]"Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 291.

[DN]In the third chapter we saw that in such cases not only are there an enormous number of ova produced, but that (e.g. in aurelia and the liver-fluke) each ovum produces, through the intervention of asexual multiplication, many individuals.

[DO]Cope, "Origin of the Fittest," pp. 226, 125, and 297.

[DP]"Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 313.

[DQ]Ibid. p. 56.

[DR]Nature, vol. xxxvi. p. 592.

[DS]Quoted from "Medical Notes and Reflections," 1855, p. 267, by Darwin, "Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. i. p. 446.

[DT]Darwin, "Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. i. p. 465.

[DU]"Natural Inheritance," p. 12.

[DV]Darwin, "Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 70.

[DW]"Organic Evolution," Mr. Cunningham's translation, p. 76.

[DX]Darwin, "Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. i. p. 104.

[DY]Similarly, from a chance sport of a one-eared rabbit, Anderson formed a breed which steadily produced one-eared rabbits ("Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. i. p. 456). This is an example of asymmetrical variation. Variations are generally, but not always, symmetrical. Superficial colour-variations are sometimes asymmetrical. Gasteropod molluscs are nearly always asymmetrically developed. Among insects, Anisognathus affords an example of the asymmetrical development of the mandible. Our right-handedness is a mark of asymmetry.

[DZ]"Natural Inheritance," p. 32.

[EA]See "Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 40, from which illustrations are taken.

[EB]"Evolution and Disease," p. 169.

[EC]"Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 8.

[ED]"Darwinism," p. 107.

[EE]Darwin, "Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. pp. 17, 18.

[EF]"Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 201.

[EG]Ibid. p. 282. The phenomena of the seasonal dimorphism of butterflies and moths show that changes of temperature (and perhaps moisture, etc.) determine very striking differences in these insects.

[EH]"Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 244.

[EI]"Darwinism," p. 293.

[EJ]"Evolution of Sex," p. 22.

[EK]"Incidental Observations in Pedigree Moth-breeding," F. Merrifield. Transactions Entomological Society, 1889, pt. i. p. 79, et seq.

[EL]Nature, vol. xli. p. 393.

[EM]See Professor Meldola's edition of Professor Weismann's "Studies in the Theory of Descent," and Mr. Cunningham's translation of Professor Eimer's "Organic Evolution."

[EN]See Darwin, "Animals and Plants under Domestication," vol. ii. p. 252.

[EO]See abstract in Nature, vol. xxxiv. p. 515.

[EP]See Nature, vol. xxxvii. p. 557.

[EQ]"Sense-Organs and Perception of Fishes:" Journal of Marine Biological Association, New Series, vol. i. No. 3, p. 225.

[ER]Nature, vol. xlii. p. 201.

[ES]Nature, vol. xxxvi. p. 273.

[ET]Journal of Marine Biological Association, New Series, vol. i. No. 3, p. 235.

[EU]Mr. S. Klein mentions a similar fact in connection with Bombyx quercus (Nature, vol. xxxv. p. 282).

[EV]Journal of Marine Biological Association, New Series, vol. i. No. 2, p. 211.

[EW]A friend of mine informs me that his limit is about 17,500 per second, 20,000 being quite inaudible.

[EX]Journal of Marine Biological Association, New Series, vol. i. No. 3, p. 251.

[EY]Of course, anglers will say that what may be true for pollack and other coarse and vulgar sea-fish does not apply to King Salmon or Prince Trout.

[EZ]"Senses of Animals," p. 117.

[FA]See a very interesting and lucid paper by Professor Crum Brown, whose name is intimately connected with this subject, in Nature, vol. xl. p. 449.

[FB]It is interesting to note that in the blind-fish (Amblyopsis spelÆus) the semicircular canals are, according to Wyman, unusually large.

[FC]The dampers must, of course, be lifted by depressing the loud pedal.

[FD]"Special Physiology," p. 636.

[FE]A band and not a line, because R. is unstable to the impact of a considerable range of light-vibrations.

[FF]Mr. Chattock has kindly supplied me with the following note:—

"Readings at the violet end were taken at the extremity of the lavender rays, at the point where the faint band of lavender light seemed to end off about half-way across the field of view (the cross-wires being invisible).

"At the red end the cross-wires were always visible, and were in each case set to the point where the top horizontal edge of the spectrum lost its definition.

"Other things equal, the 'red' readings should be more reliable than the violet, therefore, from the greater definiteness of the point observed, and the means of observing it. But against this has to be set off the fact that the extreme violet rays were spread out by the prism used more than eight times as much as the red rays.

"In any case, the wide differences observed in the 'red' readings are much greater than could have been due to misunderstanding or careless observation—as shown by setting the instrument to maximum and minimum readings, and noting the very obvious difference between them apparent to a normal eye. The same conclusion is rather borne out by the closer (average) agreement between the two eyes of the same individual than between those of different persons.

"The source of light was the central portion of an ordinary Argand burner."

[FG]The variations above indicated throw light on a fact to which Lord Rayleigh has directed attention. The yellow of the spectrum may be matched by a blending of spectral red and spectral green; but the proportions in which these spectral colours must be mixed differ for different individuals. The complementary colours for different individuals are also not precisely the same.

[FH]"Colour-Vision and Colour-Blindness," R. Brudenell Carter (Nature, vol. xlii. p. 56).

[FI]Journal of Marine Biological Association, New Series, vol. i. Nos. 2 and 3. His experiments with regard to the colour-sense in fishes gave, for the most part, negative results.

[FJ]We must remember how largely the antennÆ are used when an insect is finding its way about. Watch, for example, a wasp as it climbs over your plate. If the antennÆ be removed, it seems to stumble about blindly. The antennÆ seem almost to take the place of eyes at close quarters.

[FK]"Senses of Animals," p. 194.

[FL]See Nature, vol. xli. p. 407.

[FM]Chap. x. p. 202.

[FN]The observations are not yet published, and I have to thank Lord Rayleigh for his courtesy in allowing me to make use of this fact.

[FO]Professor Langley finds that the maximum effect with a radiating

source at 170° C. is at about 5.0 thousandths of a millimetre wave-length.
" 100° C. "" 7.5 """
" 0° C. "" 11.0 """

We are sensitive to radiations from a body at 100° C. But when the temperature falls below the normal temperature of the body we are not sensitive to heat-vibrations, but to loss of heat from the surface exposed. The limit of sensibility to heat-vibrations, therefore, probably lies between 7.5 and 11 thousandths of a millimetre. I have taken about 9.25 as the limit.

[FP]I use this term in a broad sense, as the process involved in the formation of what I shall term constructs.

[FQ]And I may add it is not an easy matter to explain to those who have not considered such questions. It is a matter of the correlation of the testimony of the sense-organs. A boy stands before me. I go to him and touch him, and pass my hands downwards from head to foot. Then I stand a little way off and look at him. His image on my retina is inverted. But as I run my eye over him I direct my eye downwards to his feet and upwards to his head. I am not conscious that the stimuli are running upwards along the retinal image. Thus my eye-muscles and my other muscular and tactile sensations seem to tell me that he is one way upwards. The image on my retina tells me, though I am not conscious of the fact, that he is the other way upwards. But he cannot be both! The testimony of one sense has to give way. One standard or the other has to be adopted. Practically that of touch and the muscular sensations is unconsciously selected, and sight-sensations are habitually interpreted in terms of this standard. So long as the two are sufficiently accurately correlated, the practical requirements of the case are met. And it is well known that it is not difficult, with a little practice, to establish a new correlation. This is indeed done every day by the microscopist, for whom the images are all reversed by his instrument. He very soon learns, however, that to move the object, as seen, to the left, he must push it to the right. A new correlation is rapidly and correctly established.

[FR]I use this term because the word "percept" is used in different senses by different writers, e.g. by Mr. Mivart and Mr. Romanes.

[FS]"Let the perception be considered to be made up of x + y; x being the ego, or self, and y the object. The mind has the power of supplying its own - x, and so we get (through the imagination of the mind and the object) x + y - x, or y pure and simple" (Mivart, "On Truth," p. 135). Mr. Mivart devotes a whole section of this work to the defence of ordinary common-sense realism. The above assertion seems to contain the essence of his teaching in the matter.

[FT]If it be said that the object does exist independently of man, though not in the phenomenal guise under which we know it, I would reply—Not so; for it is to the existence under this phenomenal guise that we apply the word "object." In philosophical language, the existence, stripped of its phenomenal aspect, is called the Ding an sich. Its essential character is its independence of man; and hence its unknowability.

[FU]I avoid, for the present, the use of the terms "abstraction" and "abstract idea" because they are employed in different senses by different authors.

[FV]"Outlines of Psychology," p. 153.

[FW]Ibid. p. 339.

[FX]"Science of Thought," p. 453.

[FY]For compound or generic ideas "not consciously fixed and signed by means of an abstract name," Mr. Romanes ("Mental Evolution in Man," p. 36) has suggested the term "recept." In the photographic psychology which he adopts, the percept is an individual and particular photograph, the recept a generalized or composite photograph. "The word 'recept,'" he says, "is seen to be appropriate to the class of ideas in question, because, in receiving such ideas, the mind is passive." This, it will be observed, is in opposition to the teaching of this chapter, in which the activity of the mind in perception has been insisted on. Mr. Romanes's recepts answer in part to what I have termed constructs, which, as we have seen, are, as a rule, from the first general rather than particular, and in part to concepts reached through analysis. Mr. Romanes, for example, speaks of ideas of principles (e.g. the principle of the screw) and ideas of qualities (e.g. good-for-eating and not-good-for-eating) as recepts (p. 60). On the other hand, Mr. Mivart ("The Origin of Human Reason," p. 59; see also his work "On Truth") terms such generic affections "sensuous universals." It may be well to append Mr. Romanes's and Mr. Mivart's tabular statements.

Mr. Romanes.
Ideas { General, abstract, or notional = Concepts.
Complex, compound, or mixed = Recepts, or generic ideas.
Simple, particular, or concrete = Memories of percepts.
Mr. Mivart.
Ideas { General or true universals = Concepts
Particular or individual = Percepts.
Sensitive Cognitive Affections large brace Groups of actual experiences combined with sensuous reminiscences = Sensuous universals, or recepts.
Groups of simply juxtaposed actual experiences = Sense-perceptions, or sencepts.

In Mr. Mivart's terminology, the representations of the lower group are "mental images" or "phantasmata." The term "consciousness" is by him restricted to the higher region of ideas, the term "consentience" being applied to the faculty by which cognitive affections are felt, unified, and grouped without consciousness. There is a difference in kind, according to Mr. Mivart, between "consentience" and "consciousness;" and the former could therefore never develop into the latter, nor the latter be evolved from the former. For this reason (because of the philosophy it is intended to carry with it) I shall not employ the word "consentience," which would otherwise be a useful term.

[FZ]We do not speak of the filling in the complement of a percept (the construction of the object at the bidding of a simple impression) as a matter of conscious inference. I do not consciously infer that yonder moss-rose is scented. Scent is an integral part of the construct. From the appearance of the rose, I may, however, infer that a rose-chafer has disturbed its petals. The complement of the percept, if inferred at all, is unconsciously inferred.

[GA]"Outlines of Psychology," p. 392.

[GB]"Outlines of Psychology," p. 414.

[GC]Mr. Romanes adopts a different use of the terms "reason" and "rational," to which allusion will be made in the next chapter.

[GD]"Chapters on Animals," p. 9.

[GE]Or perhaps we may say, in the language of analogy, that when the germinal psychoplasm of some dim form of organic memory is fertilized by the union therewith of the more active male element of discrimination, a process of segmentation of the psychoplasm sets in by which, in process of differentiation, the tissues and organs of the mind are eventually developed.

[GF]Nature, vol. xxxviii. p. 257.

[GG]For examples, see Romanes's "Animal Intelligence," p. 455.

[GH]I use the word "arbitrary" in the sense that they form no part of the normal construct such as would be formed by the animal.

[GI]"The Senses of Animals," p. 277.

[GJ]As I understand the observations here tabulated, the twelve cards lay always within Van's reach and sight. An ordinary untrained dog would have taken no notice of them. But Van, when he wanted food or tea, went and fetched the appropriate card, and got what he wanted in exchange. In twelve days he only made two mistakes, bringing "Nought" once and "Door" once.

[GK]"Mental Evolution in Man," p. 27.

[GL]"Intelligence of Animals," p. 121.

[GM]Mr. Romanes also says ("Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 235), "This abstract idea of ownership is well developed in many if not in most dogs." By an abstract idea of ownership I understand a conception of ownership which, to modify Mr. Romanes's phrase, is quite apart from any objects or persons of which such ownership happens to be characteristic. Even if we believe that a dog can regard this or that man as his owner, or this or that object as his master's property, still even this seems to me a very different thing from his possessing an abstract idea of ownership.

[GN]Doubt has recently been thrown on this fact. Mr. Bateson has shown that some fishes do not hear well, and has suggested that the carp may be attracted by seeing people come to the edge of the pond.

[GO]Journal of Marine Biological Association, New Series, vol. i. No. 2, p. 214. I should not myself have used the word "explanation."

[GP]Ibid. vol. i. No. 3, p. 240.

[GQ]I have to thank this gentleman for a most interesting account of the intelligence of his favourite bird.

[GR]Professor Max MÜller suggests to me that perhaps the ants were frightened.

[GS]"Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 82.

[GT]Ibid. p. 48.

[GU]These fall under the "practical intelligence" of Mr. Mivart. All their intelligent activities, in his view, are performed by the exercise of merely sensitive faculties, through their "consentience." I agree to so large an extent with Mr. Mivart in his estimate of animal intelligence, and in his psychological treatment, that I the more regret our wide divergence when we come to the philosophy of the subject. I am with him in believing that conception and perception, in the sense he uses the words, are beyond the reach of the brute. But I see no reason to suppose that these higher faculties differ in kind from the lower faculties possessed by animals. They differ generically, but not in kind. I believe that, through the aid of language, the higher faculties have been developed and evolved from the lower faculties. Here, therefore, I have to part company from Mr. Mivart.

[GV]Romanes, "Animal Intelligence," p. 401.

[GW]"Animal Intelligence," p. 465.

[GX]"Animal Intelligence," p. 430; and Nature, vol. xix. p. 409.

[GY]"Animal Intelligence," p. 497.

[GZ]Mr. Romanes regards it as, in the case of the capuchin, a recept. But when he speaks of a generic idea of causation, and generic ideas of principles, and of qualities as recepts, I find it exceedingly difficult to follow him. They seem to me to be concepts supposed to be formed in the absence of language.

[HA]Page 54.

[HB]Vol. xx. p. 96.

[HC]Nature, vol. xxi. p. 34.

[HD]Romanes, "Animal Intelligence," p. 17: Definition of reason.

[HE]"Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 318.

[HF]"Lessons from Nature," pp. 226, 227.

[HG]"Physiological Æsthetics:" chapter on "Pleasure and Pain."

[HH]All of these, at any rate, satisfy Mr. Herbert Spencer's definition. Pleasure he describes as a feeling which we seek to bring into consciousness and retain there; pain, as a feeling which we seek to get out of consciousness and keep out.

[HI]"Types of Ethical Theory," vol. ii. p. 350.

[HJ]Such consciousness of activity is probably associated with the innervation of afferent, not efferent, nerves.

[HK]Journal of Marine Biological Association, New Series, vol. i. No. 2, pp. 216, 217.

[HL]"Outlines of Psychology," p. 481.

[HM]Ibid. p. 494.

[HN]Page 70.

[HO]Page 104.

[HP]Nature, vol. xxxvii. p. 619.

[HQ]Vol. i. p. 310, under date 1876.

[HR]"Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 318.

[HS]"Descent of Man," pt. i. chap. iii.

[HT]Miss Nellie Maclagan describes how her Newfoundland similarly took a roll to a hungry pauper-friend (Nature, vol. xxviii. p. 150). Mr. Duncan Stewart gives (Nature, vol. xxviii. p. 31) the case of a cat who used frequently to provide her blind mother with food. Sir Harry Lumsden states that during the cold autumn of 1878 some tame partridges in Aberdeenshire brought two wild coveys to be fed near the doorstep of the house. And a case has been communicated to me by Miss Agnes Tanner, of Clifton, of a thrush that pulled up worms on the lawn for a lame companion.

[HU]"Animal Intelligence," p. 440.

[HV]"Animal Intelligence," p. 442.

[HW]Ibid. p. 444.

[HX]Ibid. p. 451.

[HY]"Animal Intelligence," p. 387.

[HZ]"Animal Intelligence," p. 486.

[IA]Ibid. p. 141.

[IB]"Animal Intelligence," p. 443.

[IC]Mr. Alexander Mackennal, vol. xxi. p. 397.

[ID]"Descent of Man," pt. i. chap. iii., quoted from Brehm's "Thierleben."

[IE]Nature, vol. xxviii. p. 32.

[IF]"Descent of Man," quoted by Romanes, p. 445.

[IG]Nature, vol. xl. p. 327.

[IH]Another example of beauty which can hardly be said to have been evolved for beauty's sake is to be seen in birds' eggs. Mr. Henry Seebohm regards the bright colours of some birds' eggs as a difficulty in the way of the current interpretation of organic nature. "Few eggs," he says (Nature, vol. xxxv. p. 237), "are more gorgeously coloured [than those of the guillemot], and no eggs exhibit such a variety of colour. [They are sometimes of a bluish green, marbled or blotched with full brown or black; sometimes white streaked with brown; sometimes pale green or almost white with only the ghosts of blotches and streaks; and sometimes the reddish brown extends so as to form the ground-tint which is blotched with deeper brown.] It is impossible to suppose that protective selection can have produced colours so conspicuous on the white ledges of chalk cliffs; and sexual selection must have been equally powerless. It would be too ludicrous a suggestion to suppose that a cock guillemot fell in love with a plain-coloured hen because he remembered that last season she laid a gay-coloured egg."

If we connect colour with metabolic changes, its occurrence in association with the products of the highly vascular oviduct will not be surprising. Some guidance is, however, on the principles advocated in Chapter VI., required to maintain a standard of coloration. In many cases such guidance is found in protective selection, as in the plover's eggs in our frontispiece. In the guillemot's egg such protective selection seems to be absent, and, as Mr. Seebohm himself says, "no eggs exhibit such a variety of colour."

In our present connection, however, the point to be noticed is that many eggs are undoubtedly beautiful. But they cannot have been in any way selected for the sake of their beauty.

[II]"Outlines of Psychology," p. 537.

[IJ]I should add, "or as conceptual thought."

[IK]This paragraph is quoted from the author's "Springs of Conduct," p. 263.

[IL]Page 347.

[IM]I have said nothing about the emotions of invertebrates, because I have nothing special to say. They have, no doubt, emotions analogous to fear, anger, and so on. But it is difficult to interpret their actions. The "angry" wasp is, perhaps, a good deal more frightened than furious. Sir John Lubbock's interesting experiments seem to show that ants have what is termed the instinct of play. But this admirable observer has rendered it probable that sympathy and affection in ants and bees have been somewhat exaggerated.

[IN]I use the term "incomplete," and not "imperfect," because Mr. Romanes, in his admirable discussion of the subject, applies the term "imperfect instinct" to cases where the instinct is not perfectly adapted to the end in view (see "Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 167).

[IO]Macmillan's Magazine, February, 1873. Professor Eimer, in his "Organic Evolution" (English translation, p. 245), narrates similar experiences.

[IP]Mr. W. Larden states, in Nature (vol. xlii.), that his brother extracted, from the oviduct of a Vivora de la Cruz snake in the West Indies, two young snakelets six inches long. Both, though thus from their mother's oviduct untimely ripped, threatened to strike, and made the burring noise with the tail, characteristic of the snake.

[IQ]Dr. McCook confirms the observation that the clearings are kept clean, that the ant-rice alone is permitted to grow on them, and that the produce of this crop is carefully harvested; but he thinks that the ant-rice sows itself, and is not actually planted by the ants (see Sir John Lubbock's "Scientific Lectures," 2nd edit., p. 112).

[IR]The experiments, both of Sir John Lubbock and Mr. Romanes, show that the homing instinct of bees is largely the result of individual observation. Taken to the seashore at no great distance from the hive, where the objects around them, however, were unfamiliar (since the seashore is not the place where flowers and nectar are to be found), the bees were nonplussed and lost their way. Similarly, the migration of birds "is now," according to Mr. Wallace, "well ascertained to be effected by means of vision, long flights being made on bright moonlight nights, when the birds fly very high, while on cloudy nights they fly low, and then often lose their way" ("Darwinism," p. 442). This, of course, does not explain the migratory instinct—the internal prompting to migrate—but it indicates that the carrying out of the migratory impulse is, in part at least, intelligent.

[IS]"Animal Intelligence," p. 59.

[IT]The American expression, "I guess," is often far truer to fact than its English equivalent, "I think."

[IU]"Mental Evolution in Animals," pp. 73, 74.

[IV]"Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 177.

[IW]Nature, vol. xxviii. p. 271, quoted in "Mental Evolution in Animals," footnote, p. 196.

[IX]"Organic Evolution," pp. 223, 224.

[IY]Ibid. p. 263.

[IZ]Ibid. p. 303.

[JA]Ibid. p. 258.

[JB]Ibid. p. 279.

[JC]Ibid. p. 276.

[JD]"Organic Evolution," p. 298. The late G. H. Lewes held somewhat similar views.

[JE]See Mr. John Hancock, Natural History Transactions, Northumberland, Durham, and Newcastle-on-Tyne, vol. viii. (1886); and Nature, vol. xxxiii. p. 519.

[JF]Weismann, "On Heredity," p. 91.

[JG]M. Fabre, as interpreted by Sir John Lubbock, "Scientific Lectures," 2nd edit., p. 45.

[JH]In further illustration of the fact that purposiveness and complex adaptation of activities is no criterion of present or past direction by intelligence, we may draw attention to the action of the leucocytes, or white blood-corpuscles. Metchnikoff found that in the water-flea (Daphnia), affected by spores of Monospora bicuspidata, a kind of yeast which passes from the intestinal canal into the body-cavity, the leucocytes attacked and devoured the conidia. If a conidium were too much for one cell, a plasmodium, or compound giant-cell, was formed to repel the invader. The same thing occurs in anthrax, the bacilli being attacked and devoured by the leucocytes. "If we summarize," says Mr. Bland Sutton ("General Pathology," pp. 127, 128), "the story of inflammation as we read it zoologically, it should be likened to a battle. The leucocytes are the defending army, their roads and lines of communication the blood-vessels. Every composite organism maintains a certain proportion of leucocytes as representing its standing army. When the body is invaded by bacilli, bacteria, micrococci, chemical or other irritants, information of the aggression is telegraphed by means of the vaso-motor nerves, and leucocytes rush to the attack; reinforcements and recruits are quickly formed to increase the standing army, sometimes twenty, thirty, or forty times the normal standard. In the conflict, cells die and often are eaten by their companions; frequently the slaughter is so great that the tissue becomes burdened by the dead bodies of the soldiers in the form of pus, the activity of the cell being testified by the fact that its protoplasm often contains bacilli, etc., in various stages of destruction. These dead cells, like the corpses of soldiers who fall in battle, later become hurtful to the organism they were in their lifetime anxious to protect from harm, for they are fertile sources of septicÆmia and pyÆmia—the pestilence and scourge so much dreaded by operative surgeons." Now, if the leucocytes were separate organisms, whose habits were being described, some might suppose that they were actuated by intelligence, individual or inherited. But in this case the activities are purely physiological. The marshalling of the cells during the growth of tissue (e.g. the antler of a stag before described) is of like import. And Dr. Verworn has shown that when a (presumably weak) electric current is passed through a drop of water containing protozoa, they will, when the current is closed, flock towards the negative pole, and when the current is opened will travel towards the positive pole. The implication of all this is that vital phenomena may be intensely purposive, and yet afford no evidence or indication of the present or ancestral play of intelligence.

[JI]"Origin of Species," p. 230.

[JJ]See Appendix to Mr. Romanes's "Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 361.

[JK]"Organic Evolution," p. 227.

[JL]Ibid. p. 228.

[JM]"Colours of Animals," p. 180.

[JN]Wallace's "Darwinism," p. 109.

[JO]"Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 244.

[JP]"Descent of Man," pt. ii. chap. xiii.

[JQ]George W. and Elizabeth G. Peckham, "Occasional Papers of the Natural History of Wisconsin," vol. i. (1889), p. 37.

[JR]"Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 226.

[JS]"Darwinism," p. 76, from Nature, vol. xxxi. p. 533.

[JT]"Contributions," etc., p. 222.

[JU]"Mental Evolution in Animals," p. 222.

[JV]"On Sheep," p. 404.

[JW]In the sense in which I have used the word; not as he uses it himself.

[JX]"Moral Order and Progress."

[JY]"Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection," p. 365.

[JZ]I consider that an apology is needed for the coinage of this and of two or three other words, such as "construct," "isolate," and "predominant." I can only say that in each case I endeavoured to avoid them, but found that I could not make my meaning clear, or bring out the point I wished to emphasize without them.

[KA]"Science of Thought," pp. 286, 287.

[KB]"Science of Thought," p. 279.

[KC]I use "substance" here in its philosophical sense.

[KD]Quoted in Professor Veitch's "Hamilton," p. 77.

[KE]T. M. Herbert, "The Realistic Assumptions of Modern Science Examined," 2nd edit., p. 123.

[KF]"Science of Thought," p. 571.

[KG]Strictly speaking, of the brain; but since the brain has no organic independence of the body, it is best here to focus attention on the unity of the organism.

[KH]I ought not to pass over without notice the "psychological scale" which Mr. Romanes introduces in a table prefixed to "Mental Evolution in Animals." It would be unjust to criticize this too closely, for it is admittedly provisional and tentative. If such a scheme is to be framed, I would suggest that the various phyla of the animal kingdom be kept distinct. I question, however, whether any one can produce a scheme which any other independent observer will thoroughly endorse. And I am inclined to think that the wisest plan is to tabulate the kinetic manifestations which we can actually observe rather than the metakineses of which we can have no independent knowledge.

[KI]Contemporary Review, July, 1886. See Clifford's "Lectures and Essays," vol. i. pp. 72 and 248; vol. ii. p. 67.

[KJ]Contemporary Review, July, 1886.

[KK]"Darwinism," p. 467.

[KL]In both cases, the question to which an answer is suggested is not—What variations will arise? but—What variations will survive?

[KM]"Darwinism," p. 293. It is strange that Mr. Wallace did not apply this view to the mathematical and artistic faculties discussed in his last chapter. It is true that such application tends to undermine the argument there developed. But Mr. Wallace is far too great and conscientious a thinker to be influenced by such a consideration.

[KN]If elimination of the unintellectual (not necessarily of the unintelligent) may be excluded, and if the unintellectual increase by natural generation more rapidly than the intellectual, the general level of intellectuality must, on Professor Weismann's principles, be steadily falling.

[KO]It may also, in part, be due to "organic combination."

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                           

Clyx.com


Top of Page
Top of Page