Everything, so far as in it lies, said Benedict Spinoza, tends to persist in its own being. This is the law of persistence. It forms the basis of Newton's First Law of Motion, which enunciates that, if a body be at rest, it will remain so unless acted on by some external force; or, if it be in motion, it will continue to move in the same straight line and at a uniform velocity unless it is acted on by some external force. Practically every known body is thus affected by external forces; but the law of persistence is not thereby disproved. It only states what would happen under certain exceptional or perhaps impossible circumstances. To those ignorant of scientific procedure, it seems unsatisfactory, if not ridiculous, to formulate laws of things, not as they are, but as they might be. Many well-meaning but not very well-informed people thus wholly misunderstand and mistake the value of certain laws of political economy, because in those laws (which are generalized statements of fact under narrowed and rigid conditions, and do not pretend to be inculcated as rules of conduct) benevolence, sentiment, even moral and religious duty, are intentionally excluded. These laws state that men, under motives arising out of the pursuit of wealth, will act in such and such a way, unless benevolence, sentiment, duty, or some other motive, lead them to act otherwise. Such laws, which hold good, not for phenomena in their entirety, but for certain isolated groups of facts under narrowed conditions, are called laws of the factors of phenomena. And since the complexity of phenomena is such that it is The law of heredity may be regarded as that of persistence exemplified in a series of organic generations. When, as in the amoeba and some other protozoa, reproduction is by simple fission, two quite similar organisms being thus produced, there would seem to be no reason why (modifications by surrounding circumstances being disregarded) hereditary persistence should not continue indefinitely. Where, however, reproduction is effected by the detachment of a single cell from a many-celled organism, hereditary persistence[M] will be complete only on the condition that this reproductive cell is in some way in direct continuity with the cells of the parent organism or the cell from which that parent organism itself developed. And where, in the higher animals, two cells from two somewhat different parents coalesce to give origin to a new individual, the phenomena of hereditary persistence are still further complicated by the blending of characters handed on in the ovum and the sperm; still further complication being, perhaps, produced by the emergence in the offspring of characters latent in the parent, but derived from an earlier ancestor. And if characters acquired by the parents in the course of their individual life be handed on to the offspring, yet further complication will be thus introduced. It is no matter for surprise, therefore, that, notwithstanding Variations may be of many kinds and in different directions. In colour, in size, in the relative development of different parts, in complexity, in habits, and in mental endowments, organisms or their organs may vary. Observers of mammals, of birds, and of insects are well aware that colour is a variable characteristic. But these colour-variations are not readily described and tabulated. In the matter of size the case is different. In Mr. Wallace's recent work on "Darwinism" a number of observations on size-variations are collected and tabulated. As this is a point of great importance, I propose to illustrate it somewhat fully from some observations I have recently made of the wing-bones of bats. In carrying out these observations and making the necessary measurements, I have had the advantage of the kind co-operation of my friend Mr. Henry Charbonnier, of Clifton, an able and enthusiastic naturalist.[N] The nature of the bat's wing will be understood by the aid of the accompanying figure (Fig. 12). In the fore limb the arm-bone, or humerus, is followed by an elongated bone composed of the radius and ulna. At the outer end of the radius is a small, freely projecting digit, which carries a claw. This answers to the thumb. Then follow four long, slender bones, which answer to the bones in the Fig. 12 Fig. 12.—"Wing" of bat (Pipistrelle). Hu., humerus, or arm-bone; Ul., conjoined radius and ulna, a bone in the forearm; Po., pollex, answering to our thumb; ii., iii., iv., v., second, third, fourth, and fifth digits of the manus, or hand. The figures are placed near the metacarpals, or palm-bones. These are followed by the phalanges. Fe., femur or thigh-bone; Ti., tibia, the chief bone of the shank. The digits of the pes, or foot, are short and bear claws. Ca., calcar. From the point of the fifth or last digit the leathery wing membrane sweeps back to the ankle. The bones of the hind limb are the femur, or thigh-bone, and the tibia (with a slender, imperfectly developed fibula). There are five toes, which bear long claws. From the ankle there runs backward a long, bony and gristly spur, which serves Thus the wing of the bat consists of a membrane stretched on the expanded or spread fingers of the hand, and sweeping from the point of the little finger to the ankle. Behind the ankle there is a membrane reaching to the tip of the tail. This forms a sort of net in which some bats, at any rate, as I have myself observed, can catch insects. I have selected the wing of the bat to exemplify variation, (1) because the bones are readily measured even in dried specimens; (2) because they form the mutually related parts of a single organ; and (3) because they offer facilities for the comparison of variations, not only among the individuals of a single species, but also among several distinct species. The method employed has been as follows: The several bones have been carefully measured in millimetres,[O] and all the bones tabulated for each species. Such tables of figures are here given in a condensed form for three species of bats.
Transcriber's note: In the preceding table some headings have been shortened to save space. The key is as follows:
If the mouse is held over the abbreviation, the full text appears. It would be troublesome to the reader to pick out the Fig. 13, for example, deals with the common large noctule bat, which may often be seen flying high up on summer evenings. Now, the mean length of the radius and ulna in eleven individuals was 51.5 millimetres. Suppose all the eleven bats had this bone (for the two bones form practically one piece) of exactly the same length. There would then be no variation. We may express this supposed uniformity by the straight horizontal line running across the part of the figure dealing with the radius and ulna. Practically the eleven bats measured did not have this bone of the same length; in some of them it was longer, in others it was shorter than the mean. Let us run through the eleven bats (which are represented by the numbers at the head of the table) with regard to this bone. The first fell below the average by a millimetre and a half, the length being fifty millimetres. This is expressed in the table by placing a dot or point three quarters of a division below the mean line. Each division on the table represents two millimetres, or, in other words, the distance between any two horizontal lines stands for two millimetres measured. Half a division, therefore, is equivalent to one measured millimetre; a quarter of a division to half a millimetre. The measurements are all made to the nearest half-millimetre. The second bat fell short of the mean by one millimetre. The bone measured 50.5 millimetres. The third exceeded the mean by a millimetre and a half; the fourth, by three millimetres and a half. The fifth was a millimetre and a half above the mean; and the sixth and seventh were both half a millimetre over the mean. The eighth fell short by half a millimetre; the ninth and tenth by a millimetre and a half; and the eleventh by two millimetres and a half. The points have been connected together by lines, so as to give a curve of variation for this bone. Fig 13.—The noctule (Vesperugo noctula). Fig. 14.—The long-eared bat (Plecotus auritus). Fig. 15.—The pipistrelle (Vesperugo pipistrellus). Fig. 16.—The whiskered bat (Vespertilio mystacinus). Now, it may be said that, since some bats run larger than others, such variation is only to be expected. That is true. But if the bones of the wing all varied equally, all the curves would be similar. That is clearly not the case. The second metacarpal is the same length in 5 and 6. But the third metacarpal is two millimetres shorter in 6 than in 5. In 10 the radius and ulna are longer than in 11; but the second metacarpal is shorter in 10 than in 11. A simple inspection of the table as a whole will show that there is a good deal of independent variation among the bones. The amount of variation is itself variable, and in some cases is not inconsiderable. In the long-eared bats 4 and 5 in Fig. 14, the phalanges of the third digit measured 26.5 millimetres in 4, and 34 millimetres in 5—a difference of more than 28 per cent. This is unusually large, and it is possible that there may have been some slight error in the measurements.[P] A difference of 10 or 12 per cent. is, however, not uncommon. In any case, the observations here tabulated show (1) that variations of not inconsiderable amount occur among the related bones of the bat's wing; and (2) that these variations are to a considerable extent independent of each other. So far we have compared a series of individuals of the same species of bat, each table in Figs. 13-16 dealing with a distinct species. Let us now compare the different species with each other. To effect such a comparison, we must take some one bone as our standard, and we must level up our bats for the purposes of tabulation. I have selected the radius and ulna as the standard. In both the Fig. 17.—Variations adjusted to the standard of the noctule. Compared with this as a standard, the mean length of the second metacarpal in the seven species is forty-three millimetres; that of the third metacarpal, forty-four millimetres; and so on. The amount by which each species exceeds or falls short of the mean is shown on the table, and the points are joined up as before. Here, again, the table gives the actual measurements in each case. For example, if the mean length of the third metacarpal of the greater horseshoe bat be required, it is seen by the table to fall short of the mean by four horizontal divisions and a quarter, that is to say, by eight millimetres and a half. The length is therefore (44 - 8-1/2) 35.5 millimetres. Now, it will be seen from the table that the variation in the mean length of the bones in different species is much greater than the individual variations in the members of the same species. The table also brings out in an interesting way the variation in the general character of the wing. The noctule, for example, is especially strong in the development of the second and third metacarpals, the phalanges of the third digit being also a little above the On the other hand, the horseshoe bats fail conspicuously in the second and third metacarpals, though they make up somewhat in the corresponding digits. On the whole, the wing is deficient in length. But the phalanges of the fourth and fifth digits, and the length of the hind limb represented by the tibia, give a corresponding increase of breadth. The wing is, therefore, relatively short and broad. The long-eared bat, again, has the third metacarpal and its digits somewhat above the mean, and therefore a somewhat more than average length. But it has the fifth metacarpal with its digit and also the tibia decidedly above the mean, and therefore more than average breadth. Without possessing the great length of the noctule's wing, or the great breadth of that of the horseshoe, it still has a more than average length and breadth. The total wing-areas are very variable, the females having generally an advantage over the males. I do not feel that our measurements are sufficiently accurate to justify tabulation. Taking, however, the radius and ulna as the standard for bringing the various species up to the same level, the greater horseshoe seems to have decidedly the largest wing-area; the noctule stands next; then come the lesser horseshoe and the long-eared bat; somewhat lower stands the hairy-armed bat; while the pipistrelle and the whiskered bat (both small species) stand lowest.[Q] Sufficient has now been said in illustration of the fact As before mentioned, Mr. Wallace has collected and tabulated other observations on size and length variations. And in addition to such variations, there are the numerous colour-variations that do not admit of being so readily tabulated. Mr. Cockerell tells us that among snail-shells, taking variations of banding alone, he knows of 252 varieties of Helix nemoralis and 128 of H. hortensis.[R] That variations do occur under nature is thus unquestionable. And it is clear that all variations necessarily fall under one of three categories. Either they are of advantage to the organism in which they occur; or they are disadvantageous; or they are neutral, neither advantageous nor disadvantageous to the animal in its course through life. We must next revert to the fact to which attention was drawn in the last chapter, that every species is tending, through natural generation, to increase in numbers. Even in the case of the slow-breeding elephant, the numbers tend to increase threefold in each generation; for a single pair of elephants give birth to three pairs of young. In many animals the tendency is to increase ten, twenty, or thirtyfold in every generation; while among fishes, amphibians, and great numbers of the lower organisms, the tendency is to multiply by a hundredfold, a thousandfold, or even in some cases ten thousandfold. But, as before noticed, this is only a tendency. The law of increase is a law of one factor in life's phenomena, the reproductive factor. In any Now, the high death-rate is, to a large extent among the lower organisms and in a less degree among higher animals, the result of indiscriminate destruction. When the ant-bear swallows a tongue-load of ants, when the Greenland whale engulfs some hundreds of thousands of fry at a gulp, when the bear or the badger destroys whole nests of bees,—in such cases there is wholesale and indiscriminate destruction. Those which are thus destroyed are nowise either better or worse than those which escape. At the edge of a coral reef minute, active, free-swimming coral embryos are set free in immense numbers. Presently they settle down for life. Some settle on a muddy bottom, others in too great a depth of water. These are destroyed. The few which take up a favourable position survive. But they are no better than their less fortunate neighbours. The destruction is indiscriminate. So, too, among fishes Even making all due allowance, however, for this indiscriminate destruction—which is to a large extent avoided by those higher creatures which foster their young—there remain more individuals than suffice to keep up the normal numbers of the species. Among these there arises a struggle for existence, and hence what Darwin named natural selection. "How will the struggle for existence"—I quote, with some omissions, the words of Darwin—"act in regard to variation? Can the principle of selection, which is so potent in the hands of man, apply under nature? I think that we shall see that it can act most efficiently. Let the endless number of slight variations and individual differences be borne in mind; as well as the strength of the hereditary tendency. Let it also be borne in mind how infinitely complex and close-fitting are the mutual relations of all organic beings to each other and to their physical conditions of life; and consequently what infinitely varied "The principle of selection," says Darwin, elsewhere, "may conveniently be divided into three kinds. Methodical selection is that which guides a man who systematically endeavours to modify a breed according to some predetermined standard. Unconscious selection is that which follows from men naturally preserving the most valued and destroying the less valued individuals, without any thought of altering the breed. Lastly, we have Natural selection, which implies that the individuals which are best fitted for the complex and in the course of ages changing conditions to which they are exposed, generally survive and procreate their kind."[U] I venture to think that there is a more logical division than this. A man who is dealing with animals or plants under domestication may proceed by one of two well-contrasted methods. He may either select the most satisfactory Under nature both methods are operative, but in very different degrees. Although the insect may select the brightest flowers, or the hen-bird the gaudiest or most tuneful mate, the survival of the fittest under nature is in the main the net result of the slow and gradual process of the elimination of the unfit.[V] The best-adapted are not, save in exceptional cases, selected; but the ill-adapted are weeded out and eliminated. And this distinction seems to me of sufficient importance to justify my suggestion that natural selection be subdivided under two heads—natural elimination, of widespread occurrence throughout the animal world; and selection proper, involving the element of individual or special choice. The term "natural elimination" for the major factor serves definitely to connect the natural process with that struggle for existence out of which it arises. The struggle for existence is indeed the reaction of the organic world called forth by the action of natural elimination. Organisms are tending to increase in geometrical ratio. There is not Elimination through the action of surrounding physical conditions, taken generally, deals with the very groundwork or basis of animal life. There are certain elementary mechanical conditions which must be fulfilled by every organism however situated. Any animal which fails to fulfil these conditions will be speedily eliminated. There are also local conditions which must be adequately met. Certain tropical animals, if transferred to temperate or sub-Arctic regions, are unable to meet the requirements of the new climatic conditions, and rapidly or gradually die. Fishes which live under the great pressure of the deep sea are killed by the expansion of the gases in their tissues when they are brought to the surface. Many fresh-water animals are killed if the lake in which they live be invaded by the waters of the sea. If the water in which corals live be too muddy, too cold, or too fresh—near the mouth of a great river on the Australian coast, for example—they will die off. During the changes of climate which preceded and followed the oncoming of the glacial epoch, there must have been much elimination of this order. Even under less abnormal conditions, the principle is operative. Darwin tells us that in the winter of 1854-5 four-fifths of the birds in his grounds perished from the severity of the weather, and we cannot but suppose that those who were thus eliminated were less able than others to cope with or stand the effects of the inclement climatic conditions. My colleague, Mr. G. Munro Smith, informs me that, in cultivating microbes, certain forms, such as Bacillus violaceus Elimination by enemies needs somewhat fuller exemplification. Battle within battle must, throughout nature, as Darwin says, be continually recurring with varying success. The stronger devour the weaker, and wage war with each other over the prey. In the battle among co-ordinates the weaker are eliminated, the stronger prevail. This mode of elimination has been a factor in the development of protective resemblance and so-called mimicry, and we may conveniently illustrate it by reference to these qualities. If the hue of a creature varies in the direction of resemblance to the normal surroundings, it will render the animal less conspicuous, and therefore less liable to be eliminated by enemies. This is well seen in the larvÆ or caterpillars of many of our butterflies and moths. It is not easy to distinguish the caterpillar of the clouded yellow, so closely does its colour assimilate to the clover leaves on which it feeds, nor that of the Lulworth skipper on blades of grass. I would beg every visitor to the Natural History Museum at South Kensington to look through the drawers containing our British butterflies and moths and their larvÆ, in the further room on the basement, behind the inspiring statue of Charles Darwin. Half an hour's inspection will serve to bring home the fact of protective resemblance better than many words. It may, however, be remarked that not all the caterpillars exhibit protective resemblance; and it may be asked—How have some of these conspicuous larvÆ, that of the magpie moth, for example, escaped elimination? What is sauce for the Lulworth goose should be sauce for the magpie gander. How is it that these gaudy and variable caterpillars, cream-coloured with orange and black markings, have escaped speedy destruction? Because they are so nasty. No bird, or lizard, or frog, or spider would touch them. They can therefore afford to be bright-coloured. Nay, their very gaudiness is an advantage, and saves them A walk through the Bird Gallery in the National collection will afford examples of protective resemblance among birds. Look, for example, at the Kentish plover with its eggs and young—faithfully reproduced in our frontispiece—and the way in which the creature is thus protected in early stages of its life will be evident. The stone-curlew, the ptarmigan, and other birds illustrate the same fact, which is also seen with equal clearness in many mammals, the hare being a familiar example. Many oceanic organisms are protected through general resemblance. Some, like certain medusÆ, are transparent. The pellucid or transparent sole of the Pacific (Achirus pellucidus), a little fish about three inches long, is so transparent that sand and seaweed can be seen distinctly through its tissues. The salpa is transparent save for the intestine and digestive gland, which are brown, and look like shreds of seaweed. Other forms, like the physalia, are cÆrulean blue. The exposed parts of flat-fish are brown and sandy coloured or speckled like the sea-bottom; and in some the sand-grains seem to adhere to the skin. So, too, with other fish. "Looking down on the dark back of a fish," says Mr. A. R. Wallace, "it is almost invisible, while to an enemy looking up from below, the light under surface would be equally invisible against the light of clouds and sky." Even some of the most brilliant and gaudiest fish, such as the coral-fish (ChÆtodon, Platyglossus, and others), are brightly coloured in accordance with the beautiful tints of the coral-reefs which form their habitat; the bright-green tints of some tropical forest birds being of like import. No conception of the range of protective resemblance can be formed when the creatures are seen To cite but one more example, this time from the invertebrates. Professor Herdman found in a rock-pool on the west coast of Scotland "a peculiarly coloured specimen of the common sea-slug (Doris tuberculata). It was lying on a mass of volcanic rock of a dull-green colour, partially covered with rounded spreading patches of a purplish pink nullipore, and having numerous whitish yellow Spirorbis shells scattered over it—the general effect being a mottled surface of dull green and pink peppered over with little cream-coloured spots. The upper surface of the Doris was of precisely the same colours arranged in the same way.... We picked up the Doris, and remarked the brightness and the unusual character of its markings, and then replaced it upon the rock, when it once more became inconspicuous."[Z] Then, too, there are some animals with variable protective resemblance—the resemblance changing with a changing environment. This is especially seen in some Northern forms, like the Arctic hare and fox, which change their colour according to the season of the year, being brown in summer, white and snowy in winter. The chamÆleon varies in colour according to the hue of its surroundings through the expansion and contraction of certain pigment-cells; while frogs and cuttle-fish have similar but less striking powers. Mr. E. B. Poulton's[AA] striking and beautiful experiments show that the colours of caterpillars Fig. 18 Fig. 18.—Caterpillar of a moth (Ennomos tiliaria) on an oak-spray. (From an exhibit in the British Natural History Museum.)] If this process of protective resemblance be carried far, the general resemblance in hue may pass into special resemblance to particular objects. The stick-insect and the leaf-insect are familiar illustrations, though no one who has not seen them in nature can realize the extent of the resemblance. Most of us have, at any rate, seen the stick-caterpillars, or loopers (Fig. 18), though, perhaps, few Fig. 19 Fig. 19.—A locust (Cycloptera speculata) which closely resembles a leaf. (From an exhibit in the British Natural History Museum.)] Perhaps one of the most striking instances of special protective resemblance is that of the Malayan leaf-butterfly (Kallima paralecta). So completely, when the wings are closed, does this insect resemble a leaf that it requires a sharp eye to distinguish it. These butterflies have, moreover, the habit of alighting very suddenly. As a recent observer (Mr. S. B. T. Skertchly) remarks, they "fly rapidly along, as if late for an appointment, suddenly pitch, close their wings, and become leaves. It is generally done so rapidly that the insect seems to vanish."[AB] Instances might When the special protective resemblance is not to an inanimate object, but to another organism, it is termed mimicry. It arises in the following way:— Many forms, especially among the invertebrates, escape elimination by enemies through the development of offensive weapons (stings of wasps and bees), a bitter taste (the HeliconidÆ among butterflies), or a hard external covering (the weevils among beetles). The animals which prey upon these forms learn to avoid these dangerous, nasty, or indigestible creatures; and the avoidance is often instinctive. It thus becomes an advantage to other forms, not thus protected, to resemble the animals that have these characteristics. Such resemblance is termed mimicry, concerning which it must be remembered that the mimicry is unconscious, and is reached by the elimination of those forms which do not possess this resemblance. Thus the Leptalis, a perfectly sweet insect, closely resembles the Methona, a butterfly producing an ill-smelling yellow fluid. The quite harmless Clytus arietis, a beetle, resembles, not only in general appearance, but in its fussy walk, a wasp. The soft-skinned Doliops, a longicorn, resembles the strongly encased Pachyrhyncus orbifex, a weevil. The not uncommon fly Eristalis tenax (Fig. 20), is not unlike a bee, and buzzes in an unpleasantly suggestive manner.[AD] Here we have mimicry both in form and habit. Another case of imperfect but no doubt effectual mimicry is given by Mr. W. Larden, in some notes from South America.[AF] Speaking of the rhea, or South American ostrich, he says, "One day I came across an old cock in a nest that it had made in the dry weeds and grass. Its wings and feathers were loosely arranged, and looked not unlike a heap of dried grass; at any rate, the bird did not attract my attention until I was close on him. The long neck was stretched out close along the ground, the crest feathers were flattened, and an appalling hiss greeted my approach. It was a pardonable mistake if for a moment I thought I had come across a huge snake, and sprang back hastily under this impression." Protective resemblance and mimicry have been Sufficient has now been said to show that this form of elimination is an important factor. We are not at present considering the question how variations arise, or why they should take any particular direction. But granting the fact that variations may and do occur in all parts of the organism, it is clear that, in a group of organisms surrounded by enemies, those individuals which varied in the direction of swiftness, cunning, inconspicuousness,[AG] or resemblance to protected forms, would, other things being equal, stand a better chance of escaping elimination. Elimination by competition is, as Darwin well points out, keenest between members of the same group and among individuals of the same species, or between different groups or different species which have, so to speak, similar aims in life. While enemies of various kinds are preying upon weaker animals, and thus causing elimination among them, they are also competing one with another for the prey. While the slower and stupider organisms are succumbing to their captors, and thus leaving more active and cunning animals in possession of the field, the slower and stupider captors, failing to catch their cunning and active prey, are being eliminated by competition. While protective resemblance aids the prey to escape elimination by enemies, a correlative resemblance, called by Mr. Poulton aggressive resemblance, in the captors aids them in stealing upon their prey, and so gives advantage in competition. Thus the hunting spider closely resembles the flies upon which he pounces, even rubbing his head with his fore legs after their innocent fashion. Many are the arts by which, in keen competition, organisms steal a march upon their congeners—not, be it remembered, through any conscious adaptation, but through natural selection by elimination. Mr. Poulton describes an Asiatic lizard (Phrynocephalus mystaceus) in which the "general surface resembles the sand on which it is found, while the fold of their skin at each angle of the mouth is of a red colour, and is produced into a flower-like shape Fig. 20.—Mimicry of bees by flies. a, b, Bombus muscorum; c, d, Volucella bombylans; e, Eristalis tenax; f, Apis mellifica. The underwings of the hive bee (f) were invisible in the photograph from which the figure was drawn. (From an exhibit in the British Natural History Museum.)] We need say no more in illustration of the resemblances which have enabled certain organisms to escape elimination by competition. Once more, be it understood The interaction between these two kinds of elimination is of great importance. Hunters and hunted are both, so to speak, playing the game of life to the best of their ability. Those who fail on either side are weeded out; and elimination is carried so far that those who are only as good as their ancestors are placed at a disadvantage as compared with their improving congeners. The standard of efficiency is thus improving on each side; and every improvement on the one side entails a corresponding advance on the other. Nor is there only thus a competition for subsistence, and arising thereout a gradual sharpening of all the bodily and mental powers which could aid in seeking or obtaining food; there is also in some cases a competition for mates, reaching occasionally the climax of elimination by battle. There is, indeed, competition for everything which can be an object of appetence to the brute intelligence; and, owing to the geometrical tendency in multiplication—the law of increase—the competition is keen and unceasing. Such, then, in brief, are the three main modes of elimination: elimination by physical and climatic conditions; elimination by enemies; elimination by competition. Observe that it is a differentiating process. Unlike the indiscriminate destruction before alluded to, the incidence of which is on all alike, good, bad, and indifferent, it separates the well-adapted from the ill-adapted, dooming the latter to death, and allowing the former to survive and procreate their kind. The destruction is not indiscriminate, but differential. Let us now turn to cases of selection, properly so called, where Nature is in some way working at the other end of the scale; where her method is not the elimination of the Here we have a case of the converse of elimination—a case of genuine selection under nature. But even here the process of elimination also comes into play, for the visitations of flowers by insects involve cross-fertilization. The flowers of two distinct individuals of the same species of plants in this manner fertilize each other; and the act of If we turn to the phenomena of what Darwin termed sexual selection, we find both selection and elimination brought into play. By the law of battle, the weaker and less courageous males are eliminated so far as the continuation of their kind is concerned. By the individual choice of the females (on Darwin's view, by no means universally accepted), the finer, bolder, handsomer, and more tuneful wooers are selected. Let us again hear the voice of Darwin himself. "Most male birds," he says, "are highly pugnacious during the breeding season, and some possess weapons especially adapted for fighting with their rivals. But the most pugnacious and the best-armed males rarely or never depend for success solely on their power to drive away or kill their rivals, but have special means for charming the female. With some it is the power of song, or of emitting strange cries, or of producing instrumental music; and the males in consequence differ from the females in their vocal organs or in the structure of certain feathers. From the curiously diversified means for producing various sounds, we gain a high idea of the importance of this means of courtship. Many birds endeavour to charm the females by love-dances or antics, performed on the ground or in the air, and sometimes at prepared places. But ornaments of many kinds, the most brilliant tints, combs and wattles, beautiful plumes, elongated feathers, top-knots, and so forth, are by far the commonest means. In some cases, mere novelty appears to have acted as a charm. The ornaments of the males must be highly important to them, for they have been acquired in not a few cases at the cost Here again, then, we have the combined action of elimination and selection. And now we may note that selection involves intelligence—involves the play of appetence and choice. Hence it is that, when we come to consider the evolution of human-folk, the principle of elimination is so profoundly modified by the principle of selection. Not only are the weaker eliminated by the inexorable pressure of competition, but we select the more fortunate individuals and heap upon them our favours. This enables us also to soften the rigour of the blinder law; to let the full stress of competitive elimination fall upon the worthless, the idle, the profligate, and the vicious; but to lighten its incidence on the deserving but unfortunate. Both selection and elimination occurring under nature, but elimination having by far the wider scope, we may now inquire what will be their effect as regards the three modes of variation—advantageous, disadvantageous, and neutral. It must be remembered that these modes are relative and dependent upon circumstances, so that variations, neutral under certain conditions, may become relatively disadvantageous under other conditions. Selection clearly leads to the preservation of advantageous variations alone, and these variations are advantageous in so far as they meet the taste of the selecting organism. For selection depends upon individual choice; and uniformity of selection is entirely dependent upon uniformity in the standard of taste. If, as Darwin contends, the splendid plumage and tuneful notes of male birds are the result of a selection of mates by the hens, there must be a remarkable uniformity Turning to elimination, it is clear that it begins by weeding out, first the more disadvantageous, then the less disadvantageous variations. It leaves both the advantageous and the neutral in possession of the field. I imagine that many, perhaps most, of the variations tabulated by Mr. Wallace and other observers belong to the neutral category. Their fluctuating character seems to indicate that this is so. In any case, they are variations which have so far escaped elimination. And I think they are of great and insufficiently recognized importance. They permit, through interbreeding, of endless experiments in the combination of variations, some of which cannot fail to give favourable results. It is just possible that it may be asked—If in natural elimination there is nothing more than the weeding out of the unfit and the suppression of disadvantageous variations, where is the possibility of advance? The standard may thus be maintained, but where is the possibility of progress? Such an objection would, however, imply forgetfulness of the fact that all the favourable variations remain to leaven the residual lump. Given a mean, with plus and minus variations: if in any generations the minus variations are got rid of, the mixture of the mean with the plus It is clear, however, that the intercrossing and interbreeding which occurs between average individuals on the one hand, and those possessing favourable variations on the other, while it tends gradually to raise the mean standard, tends also at the same time to reduce the advantageous variations towards the mean. It must tend to check advance by leaps and bounds, and to justify the adage, Natura nil facit per saltum. At the same time, it will probably have a greater tendency to reduce to a mean level neutral variations indefinite in direction than advantageous variations definite in direction. Still, it is a most important factor, and one not to be neglected. It tends to uniformity in the species, and checks individualism. It may act as a salutary brake on what we may figuratively term hasty and ill-advised attempts at progress. And at the same time, it favours repeated new experiments in the combination of variations, occasionally, we may suppose, with happy results. But it does more than this. It tends to check, and, if the offspring always possessed the blended character of both parents, would be absolutely fatal to, divergence of character within the interbreeding members of a species. And yet no fact is more striking than this divergence of character. It is seen in the diversified products of human selection; for example, among pigeons. It is seen in the freedom of nature. Mr. Wallace gives many examples. "Among our native species," he says, "we see it well marked in the different species of titmice, pipits, and chats. The great titmouse, by its larger size and stronger bill, is adapted to feed on larger insects, and is even said sometimes to kill That perfectly free intercrossing, between any or all of the individuals of a given group of animals, is, so long as the characters of the parents are blended in the offspring, fatal to divergence of character, is undeniable. Through the elimination of less favourable variations, the swiftness, strength, and cunning of a race may be gradually improved. But no form of elimination can possibly differentiate the group into swift, strong, and cunning varieties, distinct from each other, so long as all three varieties freely interbreed, and the characters of the parents blend in the offspring. Elimination may and does give rise to progress in any given group as a group; it does not and cannot give rise to differentiation and divergence, so long as interbreeding with consequent interblending of characters be freely Thus a new factor is introduced, that of isolation, or segregation. And there is no questioning the fact that it is of great importance.[AN] Its importance can, indeed, only be denied by denying the swamping effects of intercrossing, and such denial implies the tacit assumption that interbreeding and interblending are held in check by some form of segregation. The isolation explicitly denied is implicitly assumed. There are several ways in which isolation, or segregation, may be effected. Isolation by geographical barriers is the most obvious. A stretch of water, a mountain ridge, a strip of desert land, may completely, or to a large extent, prevent any intercrossing between members of a species on either side of the barrier. The animals which inhabit the several islands of the Galapagos Archipelago are closely allied, but each island has its particular species or well-marked varieties. Intercrossing between the several varieties on the different islands is prevented, and divergence is thus rendered possible and proceeds unchecked. It is said that in the Zuyder Zee a new variety of herrings, the fry of which are very small compared with open-sea herrings, is being developed. And the salmon introduced into Tasmania seem to be developing a fresh variety with spots on the dorsal fin and a tinge of yellow on the adipose fin. In the wooded valleys of the Sandwich Islands there are allied but distinct species of land-shells. The valleys that are nearest each other furnish the most nearly related forms, and the degree of divergence is roughly measured by the number of miles by which they are separated. Here there is little or no intercrossing between But even if there are no well-marked physical barriers, the members of a species on a continent or large island tend to fall into local groups, between which, unless the animal be of a widely ranging habit, there will be little intercrossing. Hence local varieties are apt to occur, and varieties show the first beginnings of that divergence which, if carried further and more deeply ingrained, results in the differentiation of species. Geographically, therefore, we may have either complete isolation or local segregation, and in both cases the possibility of divergence. Another mode of segregation arises also out of geographical conditions. If variations of habits occur (and structure is closely correlated with habit) such that certain individuals take to the mountains, others to the plains or valleys; or that certain individuals take to the forests, others to the open country; the probabilities are that the forest forms will interbreed frequently with each other, but seldom with those in the open, and so with the other varieties. The conditions of forest life or mountain life being thus similar throughout a large area, and life being through elimination slowly but surely adapted to its environment, there might thus arise two distinct varieties scattered throughout the length and breadth of the area, the one inhabiting the mountains, the other the forests. In illustration of this mode of segregation, we may take the case of two species of rats which have recently been found by Mr. C. M. Woodford on one of the Solomon Islands. These two quite distinct species are regarded by Mr. Oldfield Thomas as slightly modified descendants of one parent species, the modifications resulting from the fact that of this original species some individuals have adopted a terrestrial, others an arboreal life, and their respective descendants have been modified accordingly. Thus Mus rex lives in trees, has broad foot-pads, and a long rasp-like, probably semi-prehensile, tail; while Mus imperator lives on the ground, has smaller pads, and a Protective coloration may also be a means of segregation. A species of insects having no protective resemblance might vary in two directions—in the direction of green tints, assimilating their hue to that of vegetation; and in the direction of sandy or dull earthy colours, assimilating them to the colour of the soil. In the one variety elimination would weed out all but the green forms, and these would be left to intercross. In the other variety, green forms would be eliminated, dull-brown forms being left to interbreed. Stragglers from one group into the other would stand a chance of elimination before interbreeding was effected.[AO] In the case of birds whose freedom of flight gives them a wide range, sometimes almost a world-wide range, it would seem at first sight that their facilities for interbreeding and intercrossing are so great that divergence is well-nigh impossible. And yet the examples of divergence I cited from Mr. Wallace were taken from birds, and it is well known that divergence is particularly well shown in this class. But when the habits of birds are studied attentively, it is found that, wide as is their range, their breeding area is often markedly restricted. The sanderling and knot Another most important mode of segregation among animals arises out of habitual or instinctive preferences. Where varieties are formed there is a tendency for like to breed with like. In the Falkland Islands the differently coloured herds of cattle, all descended from the same stock, keep separate, and interbreed with each other, but not with individuals outside their own colour-caste. If two flocks of merino sheep and heath sheep be mixed together, they do not interbreed. In the Forest of Dean and in the New Forest, the dark and pale coloured herds of fallow deer have never been known to intermingle.[AP] Here we have a case of selective segregation through preferential mating, and may find therein the basis of sexual selection in its higher ranges as advocated by Darwin. The question of sexual selection will, however, be briefly considered in the chapter on "Organic Evolution." At present what we have to notice is that, through preferential mating, segregation is effected. The forms that interbreed have a distinguishing colour. From this it is but a step to the possession, not merely of a distinguishing colour, but of distinguishing colour-markings. Hence, through preferential mating, may arise those special markings which so frequently distinguish allied species. They not only enable us to recognize species as distinct, but enable the species which possess them to recognize the members of their own kind. Mr. Wallace calls these diacritical marks recognition-marks, and gives many illustrative examples.[AQ] They are especially noticeable in gregarious animals and in birds which congregate in flocks or which We may here note, in passing, as also arising out of preference, how the selection of flowers by insects may lead to segregation; for insects seem often to have habitual or instinctive colour-preferences. Flowers of similar colour would be thus cross-fertilized, but would not intercross with those of different colour, whence colour-varieties might arise. It is important to note that in these cases there is a psychological factor in evolution. We have so far assumed that intercrossing of parents and interblending of their characters in the offspring always go together. This, we must now notice, is not always the fact. If a blue-eyed Saxon marry a dark-eyed Italian, the children will have blue eyes or dark eyes, not eyes of an intermediate tint. The characters do not interblend. The ancon, or otter-sheep, a breed with a long body and short, bandy legs, appeared in Massachusetts as A further mode of isolation or segregation, for which Mr. Romanes[AR] claims a foremost, indeed, the foremost, place, is physiological isolation as due to differential fertility. One among the many variations to which organisms are subject is a variation in fertility, which may reach the climax of absolute sterility. But it is clear that a sterile variation carries with it its own death-warrant, since the sterile individual leaves no descendants to inherit its peculiarity. Relative infertility, too, unless it chances to be correlated with some unusual excellence, would be no advantage, would be transmitted to few descendants, and would tend to be extinguished. The same is not true, however, of differential fertility. "It is by no means rare," said Darwin,[AS] "to find certain males and females which will not breed together, though both are known to be perfectly fertile with other males and females." Mr. Romanes assumes, as a starting-point, the converse of this, namely, that certain males and females will breed together, though they are infertile with all other members of the species. Suppose, then, a variety to arise which is perfectly fertile within the limits of the varietal form, but imperfectly fertile or infertile with the parent species. Such a variety would have to run the risks of those ill effects which, as Darwin showed,[AT] are attendant upon close interbreeding. But Mr. Wallace points out[AU] that these ill effects may not be so marked under nature as they are under domestication. Suppose, then, that it escapes these ill effects. In this case, Mr. Romanes urges, it would neither be swamped by intercrossing nor die out on It is interesting to note that almost the only particular example given by Mr. Romanes in illustration of his theory is one that involves the co-operation of one of these further segregation-factors. Suppose, he says, the variation in the reproductive system is such that the season of flowering or of pairing becomes either advanced or retarded. This particular variation being inherited, the variety breeding, let us say, in May, the parent species in July, there would arise two races, each perfectly fertile within its own limits, but incapable of crossing with the other. Thus is constituted "a barrier to intercrossing quite as effectual as a thousand miles of ocean." Yes! a time-barrier instead of a space-barrier. The illustration is faulty, inasmuch as it introduces a mode of segregation other than that in question. I think it very improbable that differential fertility alone, without the co-operation of other segregation-factors, would give rise to separate varieties capable of maintaining themselves as distinct species. That distinct species are generally mutually infertile, or more frequently still, that their male offspring are sterile, is, however, an undoubted fact. But there are, exceptions. Fertile hybrids between the sheep and the Still, though there are exceptions, the general infertility of allied species when crossed is a fact in strong contrast with the marked fertility of varieties under domestication; concerning which, however, it should be noted that our domesticated animals have been selected to a very large extent on account of the freedom with which they breed in confinement, and that domestication has probably a tendency to increase fertility. The question, therefore, arises—Is the infertility between species, and the general Sufficient has now been said concerning the modes of isolation and segregation, geographical, preferential, and physiological. We must now consider their effects. Where the isolated varieties are under different conditions of life, there will be, through the elimination of the ill-adapted in each case, differential adoption to these different conditions. But suppose the conditions are similar: can there be divergence in this case? The supposition is a highly hypothetical one, because it postulates that all the conditions, climatal, environmental, and competitive, are alike, which would seldom, if ever, be likely to occur. Let us, however, make the supposition. Let us suppose that an island is divided into two equal halves by the submersion of a stretch of lowland running across it. Then the only possible causes of divergence would lie in the organisms themselves[AW] thus divided into two equal groups. We have seen that variations may be advantageous, disadvantageous, or neutral. The neutral form a fluctuating, unfixed, indefinite body. But they afford the material with which nature may make, through intercrossing, endless experiments in new combinations, some of which may be profitable. Such profitable variations would escape elimination, and, if not bred out by intercrossing, would be preserved. In any case, the variety would tend to advance through elimination as previously indicated. But in the two equal groups we are supposing to have become geographically isolated, the chances are many to one against the same successful experiments in combination occurring in each of the two groups. Hence it follows that the progress or In his observations on the terrestrial molluscs of the Sandwich Islands, Mr. Gulick notes that different forms are found in districts which present essentially the same environment, and that there is no greater divergence when the climatic conditions are dissimilar than there is when those conditions are similar. As before noticed, the degree of divergence is, roughly speaking, directly as the distance the varietal forms are apart. Again, Darwin notes that the climate and environment in the several islands of the Galapagos group are much the same, though each island has a somewhat divergent fauna and flora. These facts lend countenance to the view that divergence can and does occur under similar conditions of life, if there be isolation. They seem, also, so far as they go, to negative the view that the species is moulded directly by the external conditions. For, if this factor were powerful, it would override the effects of experimental combination of characters when the conditions were similar, and would give rise to well-marked varietal forms when the conditions were diverse. If we admit preferential breeding as a segregation-factor (and arising out of it sexual selection, in a modified form, as a determining one in the evolution of the plumage of male birds), it is evident that the standard of recognition-marks can only be maintained by a uniformity of preference or taste. Still, the uniformity is not likely to be absolute. In this matter, as in others, variations will occur, and after the lapse of a thousand generations, in which elimination has been steadily at work, it is hardly probable that the recognition standard would remain absolutely unchanged. For, though there may not be any direct elimination in this particular respect, there might well be colour-eliminations in other (e.g. protective) respects, and the mental nature would not remain quite unchanged. Moreover, we know that secondary sexual characters are The question has been raised, and of late a good deal discussed, whether specific characters, those traits by which species are distinguishable, are always of use to the species which possess them. Here it is essential to define what is meant by utility. Characters may be of use in enabling the possessor to resist elimination; or, like the colours of flowers, they may be of use in attracting insects, and thus furthering selection; or, like recognition-marks, they may be of use in effecting segregation. This last form of utility is apt to be overlooked or lost sight of. In speaking of humming-birds, the Duke of Argyll says that "a crest of topaz is no better in the struggle for existence than a crest of sapphire. A frill ending in spangles of the emerald is no better in the battle of life than a frill ending in spangles of the ruby." But if these characters be recognition-marks, they may be of use in segregation. They are a factor in isolation. But it may be further asked—What is the use of the segregation? Wherein lies the utility of the divergence into two forms? This question, however, involves a complete change of view-point. The question before us is whether specific characters are of use to the In any case, we are dealing at present with the utility of specific characters to the species which possess them; and under the head of utility we are including usefulness in effecting or maintaining segregation. Now, we have already seen that variations may be either advantageous (useful), or neutral (useless), or disadvantageous (worse than useless). The latter class we may here disregard; elimination will more or less speedily dispose of them. With regard to neutral (useless) variations, we must also note that they may be correlated with variations of the other two classes. If correlated with disadvantageous variations, they will be eliminated along with them; if correlated with advantageous variations, they will escape elimination (or will be selected) together with them. There remain neutral, or useless, variations, not correlated with either of the other two classes. Are these in any cases distinctive of species? It is characteristic of specific distinctions that they are relatively constant. Elimination, selection, or preferential breeding gives them relative fixity. On the other hand, it is characteristic of neutral variations that they are inconstant. There is nothing to give them fixity. It is, of course, conceivable that all the migrants to a new area were possessed of a useless neutral character, which those in the mother area did not possess; or that such a useless We must now pass on to consider briefly a most important factor in the struggle for existence. Hitherto we have regarded this struggle as uniform in intensity; we must now regard it as variable, with alternations of good times and hard times, and indicate the causes to which such variations are due. With variations of climate, such as we know to occur from year to year, or from decade to decade, there are variations in the productiveness of the soil; and when we remember how closely interwoven are the web and woof of life, we shall see that the increased or diminished productiveness of any area will affect for good or ill all the life which that area supports. The introduction of new forms of life into an area, or their preponderance at certain periods owing to climatic or other conditions particularly favourable to them as opposed to other forms, may alter the whole balance of life in the district. We are often unable to assign any reason for the sudden increase or diminution of the numbers of a species; we can only presume that it is the result of some favourable or unfavourable change of conditions. Thus Mr. Alexander Becker[AY] has recently drawn attention to the fact that whereas for But when we take a more extended view of the matter, and include secular changes of climate, the possible range of variation in the struggle for existence is seen to be enormously increased. It is well known to those who have followed the progress of geology, that in early Kainozoic times a mild climate extended to within the Arctic circle, while during the glacial epoch much of the north temperate zone was fast locked in ice, and the climate of the northern hemisphere was profoundly modified. The animals in the north temperate zone were driven southwards.[AZ] Not only was there much elimination from the severe climatic conditions, but the migrants were driven southwards into areas already well stocked with life, and the Expansion and contraction of life-areas have also been effected again and again in the course of geological history by elevations and subsidences of the land. At the beginning of Mesozoic times much of Europe was dry land. In Triassic and RhÆtic times there were lakes in England and in Germany, and a warm Mediterranean Sea to the south. Subsidence of the European area brought with it a lessened land-area and an increased sea-area: bad times and increased competition for land animals; good times and a widening life-area for marine forms of life. This continued, with minor variations, till its culmination in the Cretaceous period. Then came the converse process: the land-areas increased, the sea was driven back. A good time had come for terrestrial life; the marine inhabitants of estuaries and inland seas felt the pressure of increased competition in a lessening area. And so there emerged the continental Europe of the beginning of the Kainozoic era. And it is scarcely necessary to remind those who are in any degree conversant with geology that during tertiary times there have been alternate expansions and contractions of life-areas, marine and terrestrial, the former bringing good times, the latter hard times and a heightened struggle for existence. Now, what would be the result of this alternation of good times and hard times? During good times varieties, Intermediate between good times and hard times would come, in logical order, the times in which there is neither an expansion nor a contraction of the life-area. One may suppose that these are times of relatively little change. There is neither the divergence rendered possible by the expansion of life-area, nor the heightened elimination enforced by the contraction of life-area.[BA] Elimination is steadily in progress, for the law of increase must still hold good. Divergence is still taking place, for the law of variation still obtains. But neither is at its maximum. These are the good old-fashioned times of slow and steady conservative progress. They are, perhaps, well exemplified by the fauna of the Carboniferous period, and it is not at all improbable that we are ourselves living in such a quiet, conservative period. On the other hand, hard times would mean increased elimination. During the exhibitions at South Kensington there were good times for rats. But when the show was over, there followed times that were cruelly hard. The keenest competition for the scanty food arose, and the poor animals were forced to prey upon each other. "Their cravings for food," we read in Nature, "culminated in a fierce onslaught on one another, which was evidenced by the piteous cries of those being devoured. The method of seizing their victims was to suddenly make a raid upon The alternation of good times and hard times may be illustrated by an example taken from human life. The introduction of ostrich-farming in South Africa brought good times to farmers. Whereupon there followed divergence in two directions. Some devoted increased profits to improvements upon their farms, to irrigation works which could not before be afforded, and so forth. For others increased income meant increased expenditure and an easier, I believe that the alternation of good times and hard times, during secular changes of climate and alternate expansions and contractions of life-areas through geological upheavals and depression of the land, has been a factor of the very greatest importance in the evolution of varied and divergent forms of life, and in the elimination of intermediate forms between adaptive variations. It now only remains in this chapter to say a few words concerning convergence, adaptation, and progress. Convergence, which is the converse of divergence, is brought about through the adaptation of different forms of life to similar conditions of existence. The somewhat similar form of the body and fin-like limbs of fishes, of ancient reptiles (the ichthyosaurus and its allies), of whales, seals, and manatees, is a case in point. Both birds, bats, and pterodactyls have keeled breastbones for the attachment of the large muscles for flight. A whole series of analogous adaptations, as the result of analogous modes of life, are found in the placental mammals of Europe and Asia, on the one hand, and the marsupial forms of Australia on the other hand. The flying squirrel answers to the flying phalanger, the fox to the vulpine phalanger, the bear to the koala, the badger to the pouched badger, the rabbit to the bandicoot, the wolverine to the Tasmanian devil, the weasel to the pouched weasel, the rats and mice to the kangaroo rats and mice, and so on. A familiar example of convergence is to be seen in our swallows and martins, on the one hand, and the swifts on the other. Notwithstanding their superficial similarity in external form and habits, they are now generally regarded as belonging to distinct orders of birds. These are examples of convergence.[BB] Animals of A special and particular form of convergence, at any rate in certain obvious, if superficial, characters, has already been noticed in our brief consideration of mimicry. In the first place, among a number of closely related species of inedible butterflies, the tendency to divergence is checked, so far as external markings and coloration are concerned, that all may continue to profit by the resemblance, and that the numbers tasted by young birds in gaining their experience (for the avoidance seems to be at most incompletely instinctive) may be divided amongst all the species, thus lessening the loss to each. Secondly, there may be a convergence of certain genera of distantly related inedible groups (e.g. among the HeliconidÆ and the DanaidÆ), which gain by being apparently one species, since the loss from young birds is shared between them. And lastly, there is the true mimicry of quite distinct families of butterflies, not themselves inedible, but sheltering themselves under We must remember that in all cases adaptation is a matter of life and environment. And these, we may now note, may be related in one or more of three ways. In the first place, there is the adaptation of life to an unchanging environment; for example, the adaptation of all forms of life to the fixed and unchanging properties of inorganic matter. If we liken life to a statue and the environment to a mould in which it is cast, we have in this case a rigid mould and a plastic statue. Secondly, the adaptation may be mutual, as, for example, when the structures of insects and flowers are fitted each to the other, or when the speed of hunters and hunted is steadily increased through the elimination of the slow in either group. Here the mould and statue are both somewhat plastic, and yield to each other's influence. Thirdly, the environment may be moulded to life. This, again, is only relative, since life never wholly loses its plasticity. The bird that builds a nest, the beaver that constructs a dam, the insect that gives rise to a gall,—these, so far, mould the environment to the needs of their existence. Man in especial has the power, through his developed intelligence, of manufacturing his own environment. Here the statue is relatively rigid, and the mould plastic. Progress may be defined as continuous adaptation. In modern phrase, this is called evolution. The continuity makes the difference between evolution and revolution. Both are natural. Both occur in the organic, the social, and the intellectual sphere. Evolution is the orderly progress of the organism or group of organisms, by which it becomes more and more in harmony with surrounding conditions. If the conditions become more and more complex, the organism will progress in complexity; but if the conditions be more and more simple, progress (if such it may still be called) will be towards simplicity of structure, unnecessary complexity being eliminated, or, in any case, Revolution in organic life is the destruction of one organism or group of organisms, and the replacement in its stead of a wholly different organism or group of organisms. During hard times there may be much revolution, or replacement of one set of organic forms by another set of organic forms. It was by revolution that the dominant reptiles of the Mesozoic epoch were replaced by the dominant mammals of Kainozoic times. It was by revolution that pterodactyls were supplanted by birds. Revolution has exterminated many a group in geological ages. On the other hand, it was by evolution that the little-specialized Eocene ungulates gave rise to the horse, the camel, and the deer; by divergent evolution that the bears and dogs were derived from common ancestors. PalÆontology testifies both to evolution and revolution.[BC] That history does the same, I need not stay to exemplify. The same laws also apply to systems of thought. Darwinism has revolutionized our conceptions of nature. Darwin placed upon a satisfactory basis a new order of interpretation of the organic world. By it other interpretations have been supplanted. And now this new conception is undergoing evolution, not without some divergence. In this chapter we have seen how evolution is possible under natural conditions. If the law of increase be true, if more are born than can survive to procreate their kind, natural selection is a logical necessity. We must not blame our forefathers for not seeing this. Until geology had extended our conception of time, no such conclusions could be drawn. If organisms have existed but six or seven thousand years, and if in the last thousand years little or no change in organic life has occurred, the supposition that they could have originated by any such |