CHAPTER 8. LOGICAL PROPOSITIONS

Previous

1. THE NATURE OF LOGICAL PROPOSITIONS.

Judging has been defined as the process of conjoining or disjoining notions. This may be put in another way: “Judging is the process of asserting or denying the agreement between two notions.” The product of the act of judging is a judgment and when judgments are put in word-form such expressions are called logical propositions.

Definition: A logical proposition is a judgment expressed in words. Just as percept and concept notions are expressed by means of logical terms so judgment notions may be expressed by logical propositions.

To illustrate: The terms the squirrel and cracking a nut express two notions, and when an agreement between them is asserted and the product is expressed in word form, then such an expression becomes the logical proposition, “The squirrel is cracking a nut.”

The following being expressed judgments are logical propositions:

(1) All men are mortal.

(2) Some men are wise.

(3) No men are immortal.

(4) Some men are not wise.

(5) No sane person is a lover of vice.

(6) Some good orators are not good statesmen.

(7) Every man is fallible.

(8) If it rains, Ishall not go.

(9) He is either sane or insane.

2. KINDS OF LOGICAL PROPOSITIONS.

There are three kinds of logical propositions; namely, categorical, hypothetical and disjunctive.

A categorical proposition is one in which the assertion is made unconditionally. An hypothetical proposition is one in which the assertion depends upon a condition. Adisjunctive proposition is one which asserts an alternative.

THE THREE KINDS ILLUSTRATED:

(1) “Every dog has his day.” Categorical.

(2) “If you do your best, success will reward you.” Hypothetical.

(3) “He is either stupid or indolent.” Disjunctive.

(4) “All vices are reprehensible.” Categorical.

(5) “Either you are very talented or very industrious.” Disjunctive.

(6) “If capital punishment does not aid society, it should be abolished.” Hypothetical.

(7) “You may go provided your teacher is willing.” Hypothetical.

(8) “No intelligent man can ignore the practice of temperance.” Categorical.

By studying the illustrations it will be observed that the categorical propositions are direct, bold, assertive statements, whereas the hypothetical are limited by conditions which make them less forceful. In the second proposition, for example, “success will reward you,” is limited by the condition, “If you do your best.” The disjunctive may be regarded as categorical in form, but hypothetical in meaning, because in such a proposition as, “He is either, stupid or indolent,” a direct assertion is made which suggests the categorical, and yet it may be implied that, if he is stupid then he is not indolent; this is indicative of the hypothetical.

Some logicians classify propositions as categorical and conditional, the conditional being subdivided into hypothetical and disjunctive. The first classification seems preferable, however, as it conforms to the three modes of reasoning.

The common word-signs of the categorical proposition are all, every, each, any, no and some, while those of the hypothetical are if, even if, unless, although, though, provided that, when, or any word or group of words denoting a condition. The disjunctive symbols are either—or.

3. THE FOUR ELEMENTS OF A CATEGORICAL PROPOSITION.

Every categorical proposition should have four elements; namely, the quantity sign, the logical subject, the copula and the logical predicate. In the foregoing categorical propositions the quantity signs are respectively, every, all and no. In any case the quantity sign is always attached to the subject and indicates its breadth or extension. For example, in the two propositions, “All men are mortal” and “Some men are wise,” the quantity sign all makes the term man much broader than does the quantity sign some.

The logical subject of a categorical proposition is the term of which something is affirmed or denied, whereas the logical predicate of a categorical proposition is the term which is affirmed or denied of the subject. In the two propositions, “All men are mortal” and “No men are immortal,” the term about which something is affirmed or denied is men, while the terms which are affirmed and denied of the subject are respectively mortal and immortal. “Men” is, therefore, the logical subject of each proposition, while “mortal” is the logical predicate of the first and “immortal” the logical predicate of the second. The copula is the connecting word between the logical subject and predicate and denotes whether or not the latter is affirmed or denied of the former. The copula is always some form of “to be” or its equivalent. When the predicate is denied of the subject, “not” may be used with the copula and considered a part of it. To illustrate: in the logical proposition, “Some men are not wise,” “are not” may be regarded as the copula.

The four elements are indicated in the following categorical propositions:

Quantity sign Logical subject Copula Logical predicate
All fixed stars are self-luminous
No wise man is going to steal
Some quadrupeds are domestic animals
Some glittering things are not gold
Some boys are not discreet
A few men are multi-millionaires
Every citizen is duty-bound to vote

The student must ever keep in mind the fact that to be absolutely logical all categorical propositions must be expressed in terms of the four elements. However, life is too short and man is too busy to speak always in terms of the four elements. Moreover, to be logical may often compel an awkwardness of expression and a lack of euphony which could hardly be tolerated. For these reasons the utterances in ordinary conversation are frequently illogical so far as the four elements are concerned, though not necessarily illogical in meaning. When it is desired to test the validity of any series of statements leading up to some generalization, it may become necessary to express the statement in terms of the four elements. The student should gain some facility in this, otherwise he may be readily led into fallacious reasoning.

The following statements taken at random from newspapers are given in the original and then expressed in terms of the four elements:

The Original In Terms of the Four Elements
(1) You came too late. (1) The person is one who came too late.
(2) I saw the swell turnout coming along. (2) The man was one who saw the swell turnout coming along.
(3) All of the men walked. (3) All of the men were those who walked.
(4) The robbers cut a hole in this floor. (4) All the robbers were the ones who cut a hole in this floor.
(5) Some of these flew away. (5) Some birds were those which flew away.
(6) The rain interfered with the attendance. (6) The rain was that which interfered with the attendance.
(7) Our habits make or unmake us. (7) All our habits are forces which make or unmake us.
(8) We all had a fine time. (8) All the party were those who had a fine time.

In argumentative discourse it is often sufficient to “think the proposition” in terms of the four elements without taking the time to actually express it.

4. LOGICAL AND GRAMMATICAL SUBJECT AND PREDICATE DISTINGUISHED.

The grammatical subject is one word while the logical subject is the grammatical subject with all its modifiers except the quantity sign. For example: in the proposition, “All white men are Caucasians,” men is the grammatical subject, while white men is the logical subject. All being the quantity sign simply indicates the extension of men and is not a part of the logical subject.

The grammatical predicate is the verb-form together with any predicate noun or adjective, while the logical predicate is the predicate word or words and all its modifiers. The grammatical predicate includes the copula, but the logical predicate never includes the copula. The grammatical predicate does not include the object, while the logical predicate always includes what is equivalent to the object and all its modifiers. To illustrate: in the proposition, “Some men are wise,” are wise is the grammatical predicate, while wise is the logical predicate. And in the proposition, “He burned the red house on the hill,” burned is the grammatical predicate, while the one who burned the red house on the hill is the logical predicate.

5. THE FOUR KINDS OF CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS.

Categorical propositions are divided according to their quantity into Universal and Particular and according to their quality into Affirmative and Negative.

A universal proposition is one in which the predicate refers to the whole of the logical subject.

ILLUSTRATIONS:

(1) All men are mortal.

(2) All civilized men cook their food.

(3) No dogs are immortal.

(4) Every man was once a boy.

Considering the first proposition, “mortal,” the logical predicate, refers to the whole of the logical subject “men.” Similarly “cook their food” refers to the whole of the term “civilized men”; “immortal” to the whole of the term “dogs,” and “once a boy” to the whole of the term “man.”

In considering the definition of a universal proposition it is necessary to keep in mind the distinction between a logical and a grammatical subject, as in the second proposition the logical predicate, “cook their food,” refers to only a part of the grammatical subject, men, and, therefore, the proposition might fallaciously be termed a particular proposition rather than a universal.

A particular proposition is one in which the predicate refers to only a part of the logical subject.

ILLUSTRATIONS:

(1) Some men are wise.

(2) Some animals are not quadrupeds.

(3) Most elements are metals.

(4) Many children are mischievous.

In the foregoing propositions some, most and many are quantity signs and, therefore, must not be considered as a part of the logical subjects. Considering the logical subjects and predicates in order, the term wise refers to only a part of the men in the world, quadrupeds to only a part of the animals, metals to only a part of the elements and mischievous to only a part of the children.

An affirmative proposition is one which expresses an agreement between subject and predicate.

A negative proposition is one which expresses a disagreement between subject and predicate.

Affirmative propositions conjoin terms, negative propositions disjoin terms. In the first the agreement is affirmed; in the second the agreement is denied.

ILLUSTRATIONS:

None of the captives escaped. Negative.

Some teachers are just. Affirmative.

All trees grow towards heaven. Affirmative.

Some people are not companionable. Negative.

No person is above criticism. Negative.

Dividing both universal and particular propositions as to quality, gives four kinds; namely, universal affirmative, universal negative, particular affirmative and particular negative. No topic in logic demands greater familiarity than these four types, as every proposition must be reduced to one of the four before it can be used as a basis of reasoning.

For the sake of brevity the symbols A, E, I and O are used to designate respectively the universal affirmative, the universal negative, the particular affirmative and the particular negative. Aand I, symbolizing the affirmative propositions, are the first and second vowels in Affirmo, while Eand O, symbolizing the negatives, are the vowels in Nego. The common sign of the universal affirmative, or the Aproposition is all; of the universal negative, or Eproposition no; of the particular affirmative, or Iproposition some; of the particular negative, or Oproposition some with not as a part of the copula. The accompanying classification summarizes these facts, Sand Pbeing used to symbolize the terms “subject” and “predicate.”

Illustrations
Categorical Propositions Universal Affirmative-A All S is P
Negative-E No S is P
Particular Affirmative-I Some S is P
Negative-O Some S is not P

Henceforth the symbols A, E, I, O will be used to designate the four kinds of categorical propositions. The propositions have other quantity signs aside from the ones used above. These may be summarized:

Quantity signs of A—all, every, each, any, whole.
E—no, none, all-not.
I—some, certain, most, a few, many, the greatest part, any number.
O—some - - not, few.

6. PROPOSITIONS WHICH DO NOT CONFORM TO THE LOGICAL TYPE.

It has been observed that all expressed judgments must be reduced to one of the four logical types A, E, I or O, before they can be used argumentatively. Logic insists upon definiteness and clearness—there must be no ambiguity, no opportunity for a wrong interpretation. From this viewpoint the four types fulfill every requirement. Their meaning cannot be misunderstood. To any one with normal intelligence their significance may be made perfectly clear. Any argument when once put in terms of the four types may be spelled out with mathematical precision. In consequence it is of prime importance that the four types not only be well understood, but that a certain facility be gained in reducing ordinary conversation to some one of these types.

(1) Indefinite and Elliptical Propositions.

It is known that every logical proposition must be expressed in terms of the four elements—quantity sign, logical subject, copula and logical predicate, consequently the four types A, E, I and O which epitomize every form of logical proposition, are expressed in terms of these four elements. But in common conversation often the quantity sign, as well as the copula, is omitted. See section3.

Propositions without the quantity sign are called indefinite, while those with the suppressed copula may be termed elliptical propositions. Both may be made logical as the attending illustrations will indicate:

Illogical Logical
Indefinite
Men are fighting animals. All men are fighting animals. (A)
Lilies are not roses. No lilies are roses. (E)
Good is the object of moral approbation. All good is the object of moral approbation. (A)
Perfect happiness is impossible. In all cases perfect happiness is impossible. (A)
Elliptical
Fashion rules the world. All fashions are ruling the world. (A)
Trees grow. All trees are plants which grow. (A)
Children play. All children are playful. (A)
Some men cheat. Some men are persons who cheat. (I)

Here it is noted that the logical form of some propositions is not always the most forceful. Often the logical form gives an awkward construction and should be resorted to only for purposes of logical argument.

The reduction of either kind to the logical form must be determined by the meaning of the proposition. As a usual thing the indefinite is universal (either an Aor anE) in meaning, while the problem of the elliptical is to give it in terms of the copula, expressed with as little awkwardness as possible.

General truths, because attended with no quantity sign, might be classed as indefinite propositions, though their universality is so apparent that they may be unhesitatingly classed as universals.

ILLUSTRATIONS:

“Things equal to the same thing are equal to each other.”

“Trees grow in direct opposition to gravity.”

“Honesty is the best policy.”

“A stitch in time saves nine.”

Because the indefinite proposition is so frequently of a general nature, it is sometimes classed as general rather than indefinite.

Sir William Hamilton would class the indefinite as an indesignate proposition.

(2) Grammatical Sentences.

The grammarian divides sentences into five kinds; namely, declarative, interrogative, imperative, optative, exclamatory. But logic recognizes only the declarative, as it has already been seen that the four logical types are declarative in nature. Alogical proposition, then, is always a sentence, but all sentences are not logical propositions. The four kinds of sentences which are not logical propositions may be usually reduced to one of the four types as the attending illustrations will indicate:

Illogical Logical
Interrogative. Do men have the power of reason? The question is asked, Do men have the power of reason?7 (A)
Imperative. “Thou shalt not steal.” All men are commanded not to steal, or you are one who should not steal. (E)
Optative. “I would I had a million.” I am one who desires a million dollars. (A)
Exclamatory. “Oh, how you frightened me!” You are one who frightened me. (A)

(3) Individual Propositions.

An individual proposition is one which has a singular subject; e.g., Abraham Lincoln was an honest man. Peter the Great was Russia’s greatest ruler. The maple tree in my yard is dying of old age. These propositions, having a singular term as subject, are individual or singular in nature. As the predicate refers to the whole of the logical subject, individual propositions are classed as universal.

(4) Plurative Propositions.

Plurative propositions are those introduced by “most,” “few,” “a few,” or equivalent quantity signs. For example, “Most birds are useful to man”; “Few men know how to live”; “A few of the prisoners escaped,” are plurative propositions. “Most” means more than half, while “few” and “a few” mean less than half. In either case the proposition is particular. Stated logically, the illustrative propositions would take the form of “Some birds are useful to man”; “Some men do not know how to live”; “Some of the prisoners escaped.”

The reader will observe the difference in significance between few and a few. The former is negative in character and when introducing a proposition makes it a particular negative (O). The latter always introduces a particular affirmative (I).

(5) Partitive Propositions.

Partitive propositions are particulars which imply a complementary opposite. These arise through the ambiguous use of all-not, some and few. All-not may sometimes be interpreted as not all and sometimes as no. To illustrate: The proposition, “All men are not mortal,” is distinctly a universal negative or an E, while the proposition, “All that glitters is not gold,” is a particular negative or an O. The logical form of the first is, “No men are mortal,” and of the second, “Some glittering things are not gold.” When used in the “not-all” sense, the proposition is partitive because if the O-meaning is intended the I is implied. For example, “All that glitters is not gold,” is partitive because the statement implies that some glittering things are gold (I) as well as the complement, “Some glittering things are not gold” (O). Aknowledge of both the affirmative and negative aspects is taken for granted in the statement of either the one or the other.

“All-not,” then, is negative in any case, but universal when it means no and particular when it means not all. Any proposition is partitive in nature when the quantity sign is not all, or all-not interpreted as the equivalent of not all.

It may be observed here that all has two distinct uses. First, it may be used in a collective sense; second, in a distributive sense. For example: All is used in the collective sense in such propositions as, “All the members of the football team weighed exactly one ton,” or “All the angles of the triangle are equal to two right angles.” Using all in the distributive sense would make true these: “All the members of the football team weigh more than 140 pounds”; “All the angles of a triangle are less than two right angles.” All is used collectively when reference is made to an aggregate, but distributively when reference is made to each.

The quantity sign some is likewise ambiguous, as it may mean (1)some only—some, but not all, or (2)some at least—some, it may be all or not all. When “some” is used as the quantity sign of any particular proposition which has been accepted as logical, the second meaning, “some at least,” is always implied. This interpretation of “some” will be explained more in detail in a succeeding section.

When some is used in the sense of some only, the partitive nature of the proposition is apparent, as both Iand Oare implied. For example, with reference to the human family, to say that “some only are wise” necessitates an investigation, which leads to the discovery that some are wise, while others are not wise. If the proposition be an I, then its complementary Ois implied, or if it be an O, the Iis implied.

Few given as a sign of a plurative proposition also serves as a sign of the partitive. The plurative aspect is prominent when it is said that “Few men can be millionaires” and emphasis is placed upon the meaning that “Most men cannot be millionaires.” But when emphasis is given to “few,” as meaning few only rather than the most are not, then the Iand the Oare both implied; e.g., Some men become millionaires, but the most do not.

To put it in a word, “all-not,” “some” and “few” introduce partitive propositions when the meaning implies both an Iand anO. When treating such in logic the meaning which seems to be given the greater prominence must be accepted. Surely in the statement, “All that glitters is not gold,” the O-interpretation is the one intended; namely, “Some things which glitter are not gold.”

ILLUSTRATIONS:

(1)All men are not honest.”

(2)Few men live to be a hundred.”

(3)Some men are consistent.”

The first proposition with the emphasis placed upon all suggesting that some men are not honest, is the intended proposition while some men are honest is the implied. In reducing it to the logical form the intended proposition is the one which should be used.

With the emphasis upon few and some, the second and third propositions may be interpreted as follows: (2)Intended proposition, Some men do not live to be a hundred. Implied proposition, Some men do live to be a hundred. (3)Intended proposition, Some men are consistent. Implied proposition, Some men are not consistent.

(6) Exceptive Propositions.

These are introduced by such signs as all except, all but, all save. To wit: (1)“All except James and John may be excused”; (2)“All but a few of the culprits have been arrested”; (3)“All birds save the English sparrow are serviceable to man” are exceptive propositions.

Exceptive propositions are universal when the exceptions are mentioned. Universal propositions necessitate a subject more or less definite, as the predicate of such must refer to the whole of a definite subject. It follows that in exceptive statements definiteness is secured when the exceptions are mentioned, therefore it becomes clear how all such propositions must be universal. Of the illustrations, the first and third propositions are universal. Any exceptive proposition is particular when the exceptions are referred to in general terms or when the subject is followed by et cetera. The second illustrative proposition is particular.

(7) Exclusive Propositions.

Of all propositions which vary from the logical form the exclusive is the most misleading. Exclusives are accompanied by such words as “only,” “alone,” “none but,” and “except.” Their peculiarity rests in the fact that reference is made to the whole of the predicate, but only to a part of the subject. For example, in the exclusive proposition, “Only elements are metals,” metals is referred to as a whole while elements is considered only in part. The true meaning is “Some elements are all metals,” or to put it in logical form, “All metals are elements.” The easiest way to deal with an exclusive is to interchange subject and predicate (convert simply) and call the proposition anA.

PROCESS ILLUSTRATED:

Exclusive Proposition Reduced to Logical Form
1. None but high school graduates may enter Training School. All who enter Training School must be high school graduates.
2. Only first-class passengers are allowed in parlor cars. All parlor cars are for first-class passengers.
3. Residents alone are licensed to teach. All who are licensed to teach are residents.
4. No admittance except on business. All who have business may be admitted.
5. Only bad men are not-wise. All who are not-wise are bad men.
6. Only some men are wise. All who are wise are men.

It is claimed by good authority that the real nature of the exclusive is best expressed by negating the subject and calling the proposition an E; e.g., exclusive: “Only elements are metals”; logical form: “No not-elements are metals” (E). In a succeeding chapter it is explained how an E admits of first simple conversion and then obversion. The following illustrate these two processes:

Original E: “No not-elements are metals.”

Simple conversion: “No metals are not-elements.”

Obversion: “All metals are elements.”

From this it may be seen that the statement, “The easiest way to deal with an exclusive is to interchange subject and predicate and call the proposition an A,” is substantially correct.

(8) Inverted Propositions.

The poet often employs the inverted proposition, illustrated by the following: “Blessed are the merciful;” “Great is this man of war.” An interchanging of subject and predicate makes these poetical constructions logical; e.g., “All the merciful are blessed;” “This man of war is great.”

NOTE.—The student should not be misled by the relative clause. Often it may be interpreted as a part of the predicate rather than the subject. To wit: “No man is a friend who betrays a confidence”; clearly the logical subject is no man who betrays a confidence.

7. PROPOSITIONS WHICH ARE NOT NECESSARILY ILLOGICAL.

(1) Analytic and Synthetic Propositions.

An analytic proposition is one in which the predicate gives information already implied in the subject. Thus, “Fire burns,” “Water is wet,” “A triangle has three angles” are analytic propositions because the predicates do not give added information to one who has any conception of the subjects. Because the attribute mentioned by the predicate is an essential one, analytic propositions are sometimes termed essential propositions. Other names for the same kind of proposition are verbal and explicative.

A synthetic proposition is one in which the predicate gives information not necessarily implied in the subject. “Fire protects men from the wild animal.” “A cubic foot of water weighs 621/2 lbs.” “The sum of the interior angles of a triangle is equal to two right angles.” These are synthetic because a common conception of the meaning of the subject would not need to include the information given by the predicate. Other names for synthetic propositions are accidental, real and ampliative.

The distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions is not so clear as would on first thought appear. “Fire burns” might give added information to the child or savage who knows only of the light emitted by fire. To them, then, the proposition would be synthetic. The distinction must be based upon the assumption that the same words mean about the same thing to people in general.

This analytic-synthetic division of propositions finds a significance in the domain of philosophy. To the logician the distinction is of slight importance save in the so-called verbal disputes, viz.: disputes which turn on the meaning of words.

(2) Modal and Pure Propositions.

A modal proposition states the mode or manner in which the predicate belongs to the subject. The signs of modal propositions are the adverbs of time, place, degree, manner. Illustrations: “James is walking rapidly.” “Honesty is always the best policy.” “Aristotle was probably the greatest thinker of ancient times.”

A pure proposition simply states that the predicate belongs, or does not belong, to the subject. Illustrations: “James is walking.” “Honesty is the best policy.” “Aristotle was the greatest thinker of ancient times.”

Some logicians refer to modal propositions as being such as indicate degrees of belief. Such words as “probably,” “certainly,” etc., would indicate their modality.

As logic has to do with the pure proposition and not the modal, the difference of opinion is of little import.

(3) Truistic Propositions.

A truistic proposition is one in which the predicate repeats the words and the meaning of the subject. Illustrations: “Aman is a man,” “Abeast is a beast,” “Atraitor is a traitor,” “What Ihave done Ihave done.”

The truistic proposition is of little importance except in cases where the subject is used extensionally while the predicate is used intensionally. In the illustration, “Aman is a man,” the subject merely stands for a member of the man family, while the predicate may indicate certain manly qualities. Against such ambiguities the logician must be on guard.

In Chapter 5 the extension and intension of terms was explained. The student recalls, for instance, that the term “man” may be used to denote objects, as “white man,” “black man,” “red man,” etc. In this sense the term “man” is used extensionally. But when made to stand for the attributes “rationality,” “power of speech,” etc., the term “man” is used intensionally.

In considering the relation between subject and predicate it is customary to employ the terms in an extensional sense only, since such a restriction serves the purpose of syllogistic reasoning and conversion.

Let us, then, give attention to the extension of the subject and predicate of the categorical propositions A, E, I, O.

(1) The Universal Affirmative or A Proposition.

All S is P symbolizes the A proposition. This may be interpreted as meaning that all of the subject belongs to a part of the predicate, or that all of the subject belongs to all of the predicate. The first interpretation is the usual one and may be illustrated by the following propositions:

1. “All men are mortal.”

2. “All trees grow.”

3. “All metals are elements.”

It is obvious that the subjects of these propositions include every specimen of the particular class mentioned. For example: The subject all men includes every specimen of the human family; all trees includes every object of that class; all metals covers everything which the scientist classes as such. In the three propositions, then, reference is made to the whole subject but to only a part of the predicate, as other beings beside men, such as the horse, are mortal; and other plants aside from trees, such as the sun flower, grow; other substances, namely oxygen, are elements.

For the sake of making the logical meaning of the four propositions clearer, recourse may be made to Euler’s diagrams, so named because the Swiss mathematician and logician, Leonhard Euler, first used them.

The first illustration of the A proposition, “All men are mortal,” may be represented by two circles, a larger circle standing for the predicate, mortal, and a smaller circle entirely inside the larger representing the subject, men. Thus:

FIG. 1.

It is evident that all of the smaller circle belongs to the larger. This diagram will then fit any proposition where it may be said that all of the subject belongs to a part of the predicate, or which may be symbolized as “All S is some P.” (All the subject is some of the predicate.)

The student knows that circles are plane surfaces and when such a statement as “All men are mortal” is given, reference is made to only that part of the “mortal” circle which is directly underneath the “men” circle. Nothing has been said relative to the remaining part of the “mortal” circle.

A” propositions which may be interpreted as meaning “All S is all P” are called co-extensive A’s because the subject and predicate are exactly equal in extension. Such propositions are best illustrated by definitions; e.g.:

1. “A man is a rational biped.”

2. “A trigon is a polygon of three sides.”

3. “Teaching is the art of occasioning those activities which result in knowledge, power and skill.”

To represent the meaning of the co-extensive A by the Euler diagram, two circles of the same size may be drawn, one coinciding at every point with the other. If the first circle is drawn heavily in black and the second dotted in red, it will make clear to the eye that there are two circles.

(2) The Universal Negative or E Proposition.

“No S is P” best symbolizes the E proposition, though sometimes the universal negative is written “All S is not P.” This latter form, as has been explained, is ambiguous and therefore illogical.

“No S is P” surely means that no part of the subject belongs to any part of the predicate and no part of the predicate belongs to any part of the subject. The subject and predicate are mutually exclusive.

The following illustrate the E proposition:

1. “No man is immortal.”

2. “No true teacher works for money.”

3. “No thorough student can remain unwise.”

The E proposition may be represented by two circles, the one entirely without the other as in Fig.2:

FIG. 2.

(3) The Particular Affirmative or I Proposition.

This may be symbolized as “Some S is P,” and considered as meaning that a part of the subject belongs to a part of the predicate. It has already been noted that “some” is ambiguous and that its logical signification is “some at least.” (It may be all or it may not be all.) For example, the only logical interpretation which can be placed on “Some men are wise” is, that the investigation has resulted in finding only a part of the man family wise. Whether or not all are wise is unknown as the entire field has not received attention. In no case can it be assumed that all the others are not wise.

The I proposition illustrated:

1. “Some men are wise.”

2. “Some animals are vertebrates.”

3. “Some teachers are inspiring.”

The meaning of the I proposition may be represented by two circles intersecting each other:

FIG. 3.

The significant feature of the diagram is the shaded part which represents a part of the “men” circle as belonging to a part of the “wise” circle. The unshaded part of each circle is the unknown field.

(4) The Particular Negative or O Proposition.

The common symbolization of the O is “Some S is not P.” Put in statement form: Some of the subject is excluded from the whole of the predicate. Here, as in the I, the same logical import must be given to some; e.g., in the proposition, “Some men are not wise,” our knowledge is confined to the group who are not wise. Whether or not the others are wise or not-wise is unknown.

Illustrations of the O proposition:

1. “Some men are not wise.”

2. “Some laws are not just.”

3. “Some novels are not helpful.”

The significance of the O proposition may be shown by two intersecting circles as in Fig. 4:

FIG. 4.

A similar diagram represents the I proposition, the only difference being in the part shaded. In the O proposition the investigated field is all of the “men” circle outside of the “wise” circle, while in the I proposition the known field is that part of the “men” circle inside the “wise” circle.

In comparing the four diagrams the student will note that the affirmative propositions are inclusive, while the negative propositions are exclusive.

(5) The Distribution of Subject and Predicate.

A term is said to be distributed when it is referred to as a definite whole.

In the proposition, “All men are mortal,” the subject all men is considered as a whole. “All men” stands for every specimen of the human race; not a single one has been left out. Again, the whole is definite; any one, if he were given the time and opportunity, could ascertain by actual count just how many “all men” represented.

It should be observed that if the word definite is not incorporated in the definition of a distributed term, there is afforded an opportunity for error. The attending illustrations will make this clear:

1. “All the students except John and James are dismissed.”

2. “All the students except John, James, etc., are dismissed.”

The subject of the first proposition is distributed, while the subject of the second is undistributed. Reasons: The first subject, “All the students except John and James,” is referred to as a whole and that whole is definite, therefore, it is distributed; the second subject, “All the students except John, James, etc.,” is referred to as a whole, but as the whole is not definite, the term is not distributed. Because all is the quantity sign of the second subject the casual observer might easily be misled in designating it as a distributed term.

Here it may be well to explain that when reference is made to subject or predicate the logical subject or predicate is meant. Unless this is constantly kept in mind error results; e.g., in the proposition, “All white men are Caucasians,” the logical subject is “white men,” not “men.” If the subject were “men,” it would be undistributed, as the whole of the man family is not considered, but the actual subject, being “white men,” is distributed because the predicate refers to all white men.

Recurring to the illustration, “All men are mortal,” we have concluded that the subject “all men” is distributed. The predicate, “mortal,” however, is undistributed, as reference is made to it only in part; i.e., there are other beings aside from men that are mortal, such as “trees,” “horses,” “dogs,” etc. In all A propositions of the type of “all men are mortal,” the subject is distributed while the predicate is undistributed. This relation is clearly shown by the diagrammatical illustration, Fig.1. Here all of the “men” circle is identical with only a part of the “mortal” circle. In other words, the whole of the “men” circle is considered, while reference is made to only a part of the “mortal” circle.

In the case of the co-extensive A both subject and predicate are distributed. Relative to the co-extensive “All men are rational animals,” it could likewise be said that “all rational animals are men,” or that “all men are all of the rational animals.” Reference is thus made to all of the definite predicate as well as to all of the definite subject.

In the E propositions, such as “No men are immortal,” the whole of the subject is excluded from the whole of the predicate. This makes evident the fact that both terms are distributed. See Fig.2.

The I proposition, such as “Some men are wise,” concerns itself with only a part of the subject and only a part of the predicate, consequently neither subject nor predicate is distributed. This relation is verified by the representation, Fig.3.

In the O proposition the subject is undistributed, while the predicate is distributed. For example, in the proposition, “Some men are not wise,” “some men” would indicate that only a part of the logical subject is under consideration. But the predicate is distributed because “some men” is denied of the whole of the predicate, “wise.” This may become clear by studying Fig.4. Here all of the shaded part which stands for the subject, “some men,” is excluded from the whole of the “wise” circle. But all of the shaded part is only a part of the entire “men” circle, consequently the subject which the shaded part represents (some men) is undistributed. The predicate, “wise,” however, is distributed, as the subject is excluded from every part of it. It is well to remember that not, when used with the copula, distributes the predicate which follows it.

If the student is to succeed in testing the value of arguments, he must ever have “at the tip of his tongue” his knowledge of the distribution of the terms of the four logical propositions. With this in view the following schemes are offered:

I.
Subject Predicate
A distributed undistributed
E distributed distributed
I undistributed undistributed
O undistributed distributed
II.
A distributed undistributed
O undistributed distributed
E distributed distributed
I undistributed undistributed
III.
A All S is P
E No S is P
I Some S is P
O Some S is not P

Referring to scheme II it may be observed that A and O contradict each other; i.e., where A is distributed O is undistributed and vice versa. Asimilar relation exists between E and I.

In scheme III the underline under the symbol indicates the term which is distributed.

IV. As a fourth scheme a “key word” might be adopted. Any of these three might be used: (1)saepeo, or (2)asebinop, or (3)uaesneop. The significance of “saepeo” is this: “s” stands for subject distributed, “p” for predicate distributed, “a” “e” “o” for the logical propositions where any distribution occurs. Putting the letters together gives this: subject distributed of propositions A and E, predicate distributed of propositions E and O.

Similarly, “asebinop” stands for this: “as,” a distributes its subject; “ebe distributes both; “in,” i distributes neither; “op,” o distributes the predicate.

In the coined word “uaesneop” appear six letters which compose “saepeo,” and the letters have the same significance. The two additional letters, u and n, stand for universal and negative. The interpretation of the entire word, therefore, is this: “uaes,” the universals a and e distribute their subjects; neop, the negatives e and o distribute their predicates.

It seems to me that the last word is the most helpful as it emphasizes the two facts which are the most used; namely, (1)Only the universals distribute their subjects; (2)Only the negatives distribute their predicates.

If the student will visualize “uaesneop” so thoroughly as never to forget it, he will not experience difficulty in determining the distribution of the terms of the four logical propositions.

9. OUTLINE.

LOGICAL PROPOSITIONS.

(1) The nature of logical propositions.

(2) Kinds of logical propositions.

Categorical

Hypothetical

Disjunctive

(3) The four elements of a categorical proposition.

(4) Logical and grammatical subject and predicate distinguished.

(5) The four kinds of categorical propositions.

Universal affirmative A
Universal negative E
Particular affirmative I
Particular negative O

(6) Propositions which do not conform to the logical type.

Indefinite and elliptical

Grammatical sentences

Individual

Plurative

Partitive

Exceptive

Exclusive

Inverted

(7) Propositions not necessarily illogical.

Analytic and synthetic

Modal and pure

Truistic

(8) The relation between subject and predicate of the four logical propositions.

Euler’s diagrams

Distribution of subject and predicate

Uaesneop

Asebinop

Saepeo

10. SUMMARY.

(1) A logical proposition is a judgment expressed in words.

(2) The three kinds of logical propositions are categorical, hypothetical, disjunctive.

A categorical proposition is one in which the assertion is made unconditionally.

A hypothetical proposition is one in which the assertion depends upon a condition.

A disjunctive proposition is one which asserts an alternative.

The most common word-signs of the categorical proposition are “all,” “no,” “some” and “some-not,” of the hypothetical, “if” and of the disjunctive, “either-or.”

(3) Every logical categorical proposition has the four elements: quantity sign, subject, copula and predicate.

The quantity sign indicates the extension of the proposition; the logical subject is that of which something is affirmed or denied; the logical predicate is the term which is affirmed or denied of the subject; the copula is always some form of “to be” and is used to connect subject and predicate. “Not” is sometimes used with the copula.

The statements of ordinary conversation are usually not expressed in terms of the four elements, but must be, before they can be used in testing arguments.

(4) One word usually constitutes the grammatical subject while a word with all its modifiers goes to make up the logical subject. The verb with any predicate word is the grammatical predicate. The logical predicate is all which follows the copula—it may include the predicate-word and all its modifiers as well as the modified object.

(5) Categorical propositions are divided into four kinds; universal affirmative(A), universal negative(E), particular affirmative(I), particular negative(O). For the sake of brevity these four are respectively denoted by the vowels A, E, I, O.

An A proposition is one in which the predicate affirms something of all of the logical subject.

An E proposition is one in which the predicate denies something of all of the logical subject.

An I proposition is one in which the predicate affirms something of a part of the logical subject.

An O proposition is one in which the predicate denies something of a part of the logical subject.

Every proposition must be reduced to one of the four types before it can be used as a basis of argumentation.

It is incumbent on the student to recognize these four types with precision and accuracy.

(6) There are a few proposition types which are recognized as being illogical in form. These may be defined as follows:

(1) An indefinite proposition is one without the quantity sign. It usually may be classed as universal.

(2) An elliptical proposition is one in which the copula is suppressed.

(3) An individual proposition is one which has a singular subject. It is universal in content.

(4) Plurative propositions are those introduced by “most,” “a few” or some equivalent quantity sign. These are particular in meaning.

(5) Partitive propositions are particulars which imply a complementary opposite. These arise through the ambiguous use of “all-not,” “some” and “few.”

“All-not” sometimes means “no,” while at other times it may mean “not-all.” If the quantity sign means the latter, then it introduces a partitive proposition.

Some” may mean “some only,” or “some at least.” The latter is the logical meaning. The former interpretation makes the proposition partitive. When “few” means “few only,” it is partitive in nature.

(6) Exceptive propositions are those introduced by such signs as “all except,” “all but,” “all save,” etc. They are universal only when the exceptions are mentioned.

(7) Exclusive propositions are those introduced by such words as “only,” “alone,” “none but” and “except.” In an exclusive the predicate and not the subject is distributed. Consequently the easiest way to make an exclusive logical is to interchange subject and predicate and call it anA.

(8) An inverted proposition is one where the predicate precedes the subject. Interchanging them gives the logical form.

Of the grammatical sentences only the declarative is logical.

The relative clause, though out of place, must be used with the word it modifies.

(7) There are other propositions, though not illogical, to which the logician usually gives some attention. These may be defined as follows:

(1) An analytical proposition is one in which the predicate gives information already implied in the subject.

(2) A synthetic proposition is one in which the predicate gives information not implied in the subject.

(3) A modal proposition is one which states the manner in which the predicate belongs to the subject. The adverbs of time, place, degree and manner are the signs of the modal proposition.

(4) A pure proposition simply states that the predicate belongs or does not belong to the subject.

(5) A truistic or tautologous proposition is one in which the predicate repeats the words and meaning of the subject.

(8) In considering the relation which may exist between subject and predicate, the two terms are employed in extension only, as this use best serves the interests of inference.

The extensional relation between subject and predicate of the four logical propositions may be stated as follows:

Ordinary A—All of the subject belongs to a part of the predicate.

Co-extensive A—All of the subject belongs to all of the predicate.

E—None of the subject belongs to any part of the predicate.

I—Some of the subject belongs to some of the predicate.

O—Some of the subject is excluded from the whole of the predicate.

In general it may be said that the affirmative propositions are inclusive while the negatives are exclusive.

A term is said to be distributed when it is referred to as a definite whole.

“A” distributes the logical subject only, “E” both logical subject and logical predicate, “I” neither logical subject nor logical predicate, “O” the logical predicate only. The co-extensive “A” distributes both subject and predicate.

It is essential that the student know by heart the distribution of the terms of the logical propositions. Some keyword like uaesneop may be used as an aid to the memory. This means the universals A and E distribute their subjects, while the negatives E and O distribute their predicates.

11. ILLUSTRATIVE EXERCISES.

(1a) Examine the following list of propositions with a view to classifying them as “A’s,” “E’s,” “I’s” or “O’s.”

E 1. “None of the inmates voted.”

A 2.Benj. Franklin was the best educated American.”

I 3. “Some doctors deem it right to lie to their patients.”

A 4. “All earnest teachers need to observe the teaching of others.”

I 5. “Some politicians are honest.”

A 6. “Fools rush in where angels fear to tread.”

O 7. “Some proverbs are not true to life.”

E 8. “No man should infringe upon the rights of others.”

I recall that an affirmative proposition in which the predicate refers to the whole of the subject is an A, while one where the predicate refers to only a part of the subject is an I. Further, a negative proposition where the predicate refers to the whole of the subject is an E, while one in which the predicate refers to only a part of the subject is an O. With these facts in mind, Iclassify the propositions as indicated.

(1b) In a similar manner classify as to quantity and quality the following:

(1) “All worthy workers grow to look like their work.”

(2) “Every dog has his day.”

(3) “Some of the presidents were not popular.”

(4) “No unskilled laborer can afford to own an automobile.”

(5) “Some of the ‘election prophets’ were sadly mistaken.”

(2a) Classify the following propositions and make the illogical, logical:

(1) “Only first-class passengers may ride in parlor cars.”

(2) “Haste makes waste.”

(3) “Few men know how to act under stress.”

(4) “All which seems to ring true is not true.”

(5) “Members alone are admitted.”

(6) “None but men of integrity need apply.”

(7) “Horses trot.”

(8) “Blessed are they which are persecuted for righteousness sake.”

The first proposition is an exclusive and may be made logical by converting and calling it an A, viz.: “All who ride in parlor cars are first-class passengers.” (A)

The second is indefinite and elliptical and is made logical by prefixing the universal quantity sign and expressing in terms of the four elements. The logical form is, “All who make haste are those who are wasteful.” (A)

The third is plurative in nature and means, “Most men do not know how to act under stress.” It would be classed as an O.

The fourth is partitive in nature because of the ambiguous use of “all—not.” It means, “Some who seem to ring true are not true.” (O)

The fifth is an exclusive. By converting and changing to an A the proposition takes the logical form, “All who are admitted are members.”

The sixth is likewise an exclusive, the logical form being, “All who apply must be men of integrity.”

The seventh is an elliptical proposition. Logical form: “All horses are trotting animals.”

The eighth is an inverted or poetical proposition. It is made logical by interchanging subject and predicate. Logical form: “Those who are persecuted for righteousness sake are blessed.”

(2b) Classify the attending propositions and change to the logical form, if necessary:

(1) “Only truthful men are honest.”

(2) “The stokers alone were saved.”

(3) “All who run do not think.”

(4) “Honesty is the best policy.”

(5) “They laugh that win.”

(6) “The good alone are happy.”

(7) “Knowledge is power.”

(8) “Only the actions of the just smell sweet and blossom in the dust.”

12. REVIEW QUESTIONS.

(1) Define and illustrate logical propositions.

(2) Define and exemplify the three kinds of logical propositions.

(3) What are the usual quantity signs of the four kinds of propositions?

(4) Name and define the four elements of a logical proposition.

(5) Select from the printed page five propositions which are not expressed in terms of the four elements, and so express them.

(6) Distinguish between logical and grammatical subject; likewise between logical and grammatical predicate.

(7) Define and illustrate the four kinds of categorical propositions.

(8) What makes an understanding of the four logical propositions so important?

(9) Give the unusual quantity signs of the logical propositions.

(10) What should guide one in making an indefinite proposition logical?

(11) How are general truths usually classified?

(12) Change birds fly to the logical form.

(13) How many and what kinds of grammatical sentences are logical?

(14) How would the logician deal with interrogative sentences?

(15) Give illustrations of individual propositions. How are they usually classified?

(16) Explain the logical mode of dealing with the plurative proposition.

(17) Exemplify the ambiguity of “all-not,” “some” and “few.”

(18) Why are propositions introduced by “all-not,” “some” and “few” called partitive?

(19) Use “all” in both a partitive and collective sense. Which signification has logic adopted?

(20) When are exceptive propositions universal and when particular?

(21) What is an exclusive proposition?

(22) Explain by circles the exclusive.

(23) Tell in full how to change an exclusive to logical form.

(24) Tell how the logician would deal with such poetical expressions as “Blessed are the pure in heart,” “Tell me not in mournful numbers,” “Strenuous is the man of state.”

(25) What distinction does the logician make between analytic and synthetic propositions?

(26) Illustrate the difference between the so-called modal and pure propositions.

(27) Explain and illustrate the truistic proposition.

(28) Show by circles the relation existing between the subject and predicate of all the logical propositions.

(29) State in good English the relation between the subject and predicate of all the logical propositions.

(30) Relative to the distribution of terms apply the words “uaesneop” and “asebinop.” Which one is the more serviceable?

(31) Distinguish between the grammatical and logical subject.

(32) Explain by circles the distribution of the terms of the four logical propositions.

(33) The statement, “A part of the subject is excluded from the whole of the predicate,” describes which proposition? Explain how it indicates that the predicate is distributed.

13. QUESTIONS FOR ORIGINAL THOUGHT AND INVESTIGATION.

(1) Show that a judgment may be an individual notion as well as a general notion.

(2) Many logicians classify logical propositions in this wise:

Proposition Categorical
Conditional Hypothetical
Disjunctive

Give arguments for and against such a classification.

(3) “All men are bipeds” is a judgment of extension, while “Man is wise” is a judgment of intension. Explain.

(4) “To be logical is to be pedantic.” Discuss this.

(5) Why is the proposition, “He runs,” illogical? Make it logical.

(6) Point out the reasons for calling, “White men are Caucasians,” a particular proposition.

(7) What makes it necessary to change the propositions of ordinary conversation to those of the four logical types?

(8) Some would call the individual proposition particular. Argue the question.

(9) Make a list of five propositions in common speech and show how their partitive implication may mislead.

(10) Explain by circles some only and some at least.

(11) Explain how “et cetera” may change a universal to a particular proposition.

(12) “The real nature of an exclusive is best shown by negating the subject and calling the proposition an E.” Give arguments for and against this statement.

(13) Show that with the immature mind all propositions must be synthetical.

(14) Explain how a proposition may be truistic in form but not in meaning.

(15) Show by the Euler diagram how easy it is for the careless student to think that an “O” does not distribute its predicate.

(16) Explain by the use of two pads (a small yellow one and a large white one) the distribution of terms.

(17) When the logician makes reference to the subject of a proposition, show that he should exercise care in designating it as the logical subject.

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                           

Clyx.com


Top of Page
Top of Page