1. INDUCTIVE AND DEDUCTIVE REASONING DISTINGUISHED.It has been remarked that inference is the process of deriving a judgment from one or two antecedent judgments, and that mediate inference is inference by means of a middle term. But to reason by means of a middle term necessitates two judgments; hence mediate inference might be defined as the process of deriving a judgment from two antecedent judgments. In this treatment mediate inference and reasoning have been used interchangeably. This, then, becomes our definition for reasoning: Reasoning is the process of deriving a judgment from two antecedent judgments. The syllogism results when the process of reasoning is formally clothed in words. Moreover, the conclusion of the syllogism may be more general than the premises or less general. This suggests the two important kinds of reasoning; namely, inductive and deductive. Inductive reasoning is reasoning from less general premises to a more general conclusion. Deductive reasoning is reasoning from more general premises to a less general conclusion. ILLUSTRATION:
The student who is sufficiently familiar with the canons of the deductive syllogism will at once detect the fallacy of illicit minor in the foregoing inductive syllogisms; i.e., “birds” when used as the predicate of the minor premise of the first syllogism is undistributed, but as the subject of the conclusion “birds” is distributed. The same might be said concerning the terms “metals” and “large cities.” Aportion of this chapter will be devoted to answering this criticism. At this point it may be stated that the inductive syllogism is not supposed to conform perfectly to the canons of the deductive syllogism. 2. THE INDUCTIVE HAZARD.Referring to the first inductive syllogism of section 3. THE COMPLEXITY OF THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION.The problem of induction is much more complex than that of deduction because of these reasons: First. Deduction as a process of reasoning was the only kind discussed by the logicians for two thousand years. Aristotle is called the father of deductive logic and this Intellectual Giant, the greatest of ancient time and possibly of all time, so perfected the form of deductive reasoning that, up to the time of Francis Bacon, no scholar possessed the temerity to gainsay its supremacy in the field of logical reasoning. For twenty centuries Aristotle’s Deductive Logic was the Logicians’ Bible. On the other hand, inductive reasoning, though it was briefly discussed by Aristotle, received little attention till the versatile Francis Bacon placed it upon the stage of the thinking world. This makes deduction nearly two thousand years older than induction. Time, by eliminating the personal equation and exposing in various ways fallacious thinking, tends to unify and universalize truth. Hence, logicians are agreed so far as the fundamentals of deductive logic are concerned, but are still at odds over the true conception and use of inductive logic. A second reason for this confused status in the field 4. THE VARIOUS CONCEPTIONS OF INDUCTION.The attending quotations will give the student a fair idea of the leading conceptions concerning induction: (1) “Induction is the process by which we conclude that what is true of certain individuals of a class is true of the whole class, or that what is true at certain times will be true under similar circumstances at all times.” “Induction, as above defined, is a process of inference; it proceeds from the known to the unknown.” “Any process in which what seems the conclusion is no wider than the premises from which it is drawn, does not fall within the meaning of the term.”—J.S. Mill, ASystem of Logic, 1892, p.175. (2) “An induction is a generalization or an inference based upon propositions that state observed facts.” “The truth inferred may be general or particular, but it must be one which we cannot perceive in a single act of observation.”—Ballentine’s Inductive Logic, 1896, p.14. (3) “Induction is the process of inference by which we get at general truths from particular facts or cases.”—Ryland’s Logic, 1900, p.148. (4) “Induction may be defined as the legitimate inference of the general from the particular, or, of the more general from the less general.”—Fowler, 1905, p.10, Vol.2. (5) “The term induction has been used by logicians to denote this leap of the mind from the limitations of its positive knowledge to belief in universal laws.” “In pedagogy, however, the term is applied to the whole process of arriving at general truths or principles.”—Salisbury’s Theory of Teaching, p.156. 5. INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION CONTIGUOUS PROCESSES.If there is one thing above another which modern logic is emphasizing it is the unity of the mind and the contiguity of thinking. Induction and deduction are dove-tailed processes which characterize all thinking worthy of the name. Where induction ceases, deduction commences, and vice versa. It becomes the function of inductive thinking to establish a connection between what has been experienced and what has not been experienced. Therefore, the conclusion of an induction must always contain more than is implied in the premises. The premises denote facts which have been observed; whereas the conclusion denotes the observed facts of the premises plus analogous facts which have not been observed. Inductive thought ventures into the unknown, and attempts to establish a bond of connection between it and something already known. Induction seeks new knowledge, and does so by taking that “leap into the dark” already referred to as the “inductive hazard.” As soon as the mind reaches a universal truth, it sets to work to clarify this truth. Such is accomplished by reference to other facts which the universal is supposed to include; and this application of the general to the particular is deduction. Induction discovers the new knowledge while deduction clarifies it. 6. INDUCTION AN ASSUMPTION.In this treatment induction as a general process has been subdivided into induction as a mode of inference and induction as a method. Induction as a mode of inference is the process of reasoning from less general premises to a more general conclusion; whereas induction as a method is a procedure from the observation of individual facts to a realization of a universal truth. In either case the conclusion of an inductive process always implies more than is contained in the premises. This gives to the conclusion an uncertainty. No induction is absolutely free from doubt except the so-called perfect induction, which form will receive attention in a later section. 7. UNIVERSAL CAUSATION.All inductive assumptions are made possible because of two laws—universal causation and uniformity of nature. The law of universal causation may be stated in this wise: Nothing can occur without a cause and every cause has its effect. “It is a universal truth, that every fact which has a beginning has a cause.”—Mill. SIMPLE ILLUSTRATIONS OF UNIVERSAL CAUSATION. The sun rises in the east. The boy throws a stone through the That universal causation is a fundamental condition of all induction may be further illustrated. The astronomer notes that the stars in the vicinity of Vega seem to be moving outward from a common center; whereas in the opposite part of the sky the stars seem to be moving inward toward a common center. Having observed this phenomenon, the astronomer at once looks for a cause. Finally he decides that the phenomenon is due to the fact that the sun, with his attending family, is moving towards Vega. Arranged, the argument may take this form: The stars in the vicinity of Vega seem to be moving outward from a common center, whereas in the opposite part of the sky the stars seem to be moving inward, When descending a mountain the trees at the foot seem to move outward from, and those at the top inward toward, a common center, When riding on the train the ties in front seem to move outward while those in the rear seem to move inward. From this we conclude that the sun with the Earth and other planets is moving toward a spot in the sky near Vega. Were it not for the assumption that the phenomenon relative to the stars had a cause there could have been no induction. Moreover, any investigation concerning “democratic waves,” “prices of food stuffs,” etc., must assume as a starting point that these phenomena have causes. It would appear that the mind is not satisfied with a mere passive observation of the occurrences of the world but is inclined to reach out for the “whys and wherefores.” Due partly to this reason, “universal causation” is often referred to as an a priori law; meaning that it is a law which cannot be proved, but must be assumed in all thinking. 8. THE LAW OF THE UNIFORMITY OF NATURE.Law stated: The same antecedents are invariably followed by the same consequents. “That the course of nature is uniform is Referring to the observed phenomenon of the outward movement of the stars about Vega, the astronomer might advance as an hypothesis the fact of the solar system’s movement toward Vega. Having done this he could then experiment with a view of verifying this hypothesis. In this experiment he would attempt to introduce the same cause surrounded by similar circumstances, and then watch for the same effect. To make it concrete: suppose the astronomer paints the side of a barn dark blue and bedecks this with stars of white. Then taking a position as far removed from the blue surface as his eyesight will permit, he runs toward the barn watching the apparent movement of the artificial stars. Asimilar experiment could be performed by substituting for the starred barn, the stumps on a side hill. In both experiments he assumes that like conditions will be followed by constant results. That is, in these particular cases, advancing toward a group of objects is always followed by an apparent separation of said objects. This law of uniformity of nature not only underlies inductive thinking but it really conditions all thinking. It implies that the universe is a rational system functioning in a uniform manner. Moreover, it suggests that the interpretations of the mind are likewise uniform and whenever the mind proves a fact to be a universal truth, this truth will always remain a truth unless the conditions change. In fact were it not for the uniformity of nature, all activity whatsoever would be rendered nugatory. Because of this law we have a right to assume that grinding a knife under right conditions will always tend to sharpen it; that surrounding a live seed with a proper environment will result in growth; that water at the same altitude will boil at a constant temperature, etc., etc. The student will discern the close connection between these two laws and the laws of thought. There is really no distinctive mark between the law of causation and the law of sufficient reason, while “uniformity of nature” includes identity as one of its distinctive features. The laws differ, however, in their application, Because “uniformity of nature” expresses facts of experience, it is regarded as an empirical law, as contrasted with the law of causation, which is supposed to be based upon an innate mental conception or is an a priori law. 9. INDUCTIVE ASSUMPTION JUSTIFIED.The function of induction seems to be to universalize particulars. The mind of man has ever been engaged in establishing connections among the concrete experiences of daily life. This ability of his to generalize his individual experiences has been one of the chief agencies in elevating him to the position of “King of the animal world.” In this disposition to generalize man has taken it for granted that nature is honest; that what she tells him under given conditions, she will tell him again under identical conditions. To put it in logical terms man can depend upon the invariability of nature’s activities, or upon the uniformity of nature. Here, then, is one of the most fundamental laws not only of induction but of all activity. But this law implies a second quite as fundamental. If every cause is invariably followed by the same effect under like conditions, then it is thereby implied that every cause has an affect and every event is due to some cause. This, too, is invariable. In consequence of these facts man is justified in thinking that nature is not only honest and therefore “she gives me confidence, but her every activity means something and therefore she arouses my curiosity.” “Uniformity of nature” engenders confidence, “universal causation” inspires the spirit of discovery 10. THREE FORMS OF INDUCTIVE RESEARCH.Induction is a matter of universalizing less universal experiences. In this the process may assume any one of three forms, namely: (1)Induction by simple enumeration; (inductio per enumerationem); (2)Induction by analogy; (3)Induction by analysis. THREE FORMS ILLUSTRATED: (1) Simple enumeration. Having observed a few instances the generalization is, “All birds have wings.” The certitude of this may now be strengthened by observing more birds and finding without exception that each has wings. (2) Analogy. By noting on Mars geometric markings which resemble canals, the generalization is vouchsafed that Mars is inhabited by human beings. Other similarities in atmospheric conditions, existence of land and water, etc., tend to make this generalization more plausible. (3) Analysis. By analyzing water taken from a certain spring, it is found to contain hydrogen and oxygen in the proportion of 1 to 8; in consequence a generalization to this effect is posited. Analyses of specimens from other sources yield As a usual thing the particular form which the induction assumes depends on the nature of the topic under investigation and also on the mental make-up of the investigator. The general statement that all birds have wings could hardly be derived by means of analogy or analysis, but is a matter of a casual observation of many instances. Moreover, that mind given to accurate observation, but not inclined to note resemblances or to carry on experiments, would naturally follow the first inductive type. On the other hand, simple enumeration would be impossible in questions like the habitability of Mars, and would yield no results in cases requiring definite scientific experimentation like electrolysis. It is worthy of note that some topics lend themselves to all three modes of procedure. To wit: (1)Enumeration. Without being taught the rule the child is given a list of examples involving the dividing of a decimal by a decimal and is asked to solve them. By comparing his answers with those in the book, he somewhat accidentally discovers what seems to be the correct rule for pointing off in the quotient. By following this rule and each time comparing answers he establishes the truth. (2)Analogy. If .24 ÷ .6 is the first example, the child may resort to the well known process of dividing a common fraction by a common fraction, ( 24 11. INDUCTION BY SIMPLE ENUMERATION.As its name implies this type of inductive research consists in observing many instances which may exemplify the particular uniformity under consideration. The process is quantitative rather than qualitative, the certitude of the generalization depending on the mass of facts collected rather than on any striking resemblance or any detailed analysis. The aim is to observe, accurately if not scientifically, instance after instance until all doubt is removed. The outcome of such observation may be three fold. (1)The enumeration may be complete. This gives the so-called “perfect induction” which will receive attention later. (2)The enumeration may be incomplete and without exceptions; generalizing in this way from uncontradicted experience gives what are termed “empirical” truths. (3)The enumeration may be incomplete with exceptions. It is obvious that this type of induction could give no valid generalization; but the result may be put in the form of a ratio between the uniformities and the exceptions. Such a procedure is a mere “calculation of chances” and the result simply an expressed probability. THE THREE KINDS OF SIMPLE ENUMERATION ILLUSTRATED. The subject to receive investigation is a school examination. (1) Complete enumeration. Every paper is read and marked; this leads to the generalization, “All the class have passed.” (2) Incomplete enumeration with no exceptions. Representative papers are read and marked in which no failures are found. Generalization, “Probably all of the class have passed.” (3) Incomplete enumeration with exceptions. Representative papers are read and marked in which there are 20 failures out of the hundred papers examined. Generalization, “Probably about 80% of the class have passed.” Briefly, simple enumeration may take the form of (1)a perfect induction, (2)a probable induction, (3)a mere calculation of chances. The first necessitates completed experience, the second uncontradicted experience and the third contradicted experience. 12. INDUCTION BY ANALOGY.Induction by analogy assumes that if two (or more) things resemble each other in certain respects, they belong to the same type, and, therefore, any fact known of the one may be affirmed of the other. THE TYPE. As the definition implies, analogy involves an extensive Illustrations of analogical inductions by example or type. (1) Mathematics. Example: a + b a + b ——————— a2 + ab + ab + b2 ——————— a2 + 2ab + b2 Inductive Inference: The square of the sum of two quantities is equal to the square of the first, plus twice the first by the second, plus the square of the second. (2) Nature. This corn sent me as a sample produced heavy, full ears, and many of them; hence (inductive inference), if Iplant corn like this sample under like conditions, Iwill receive in return heavy, full ears, and many of them. (3) Geography. Cities like New York, located on the coast, possess a larger foreign element than the inland cities like Philadelphia. (4) Grammar. A noun is the name of anything, as the examples, “George Washington” and “house” would indicate. In deriving a generalization from one or two examples the prime essential is to select types which are truly representative. Often the example used is a special type and in consequence does not exemplify all of the essential characteristics of the group. To teach the nature of a parallelogram by using a rectangle only, is an easy way to commit this error; or one may affirm that the class can easily cover the work, when the judgment is based entirely on knowledge concerning the brightest one of the grade. Type work when judicially used is a positive time saver and a very present help in times of perplexity. Let the skillful teacher use types and examples extensively yet cautiously. THE MARK OF SIMILARITY. As opposed to analogy by type there is a second form; namely, analogy by one or more similar marks or qualities. This form is best described by the definition: When two things resemble each other in a few marks or qualities they resemble each other in other marks or qualities. Illustrations of analogy by marks. (1) Noting that two students have the same surname, Iinfer that they are brothers. (2) A man with a book under his arm rings the door bell and asks to see “the lady of the house.” At once the conclusion is drawn that the caller is a book agent. (3) Two automobiles, resembling each other in shape of body, force one to the conclusion that the machines are of the same make. THE ERRORS OF ANALOGY BY MARKS OF SIMILARITY. It follows that analogy by example gives generalizations of much greater certitude than analogy by one or two marks of resemblance. Here is a field bespattered from boundary to boundary with erroneous thinking. The principle of resemblance being an innate tendency, this form of error is most common with the immature. The child reasons by analogy when he invests the poodle with the despised cognomen of “kitty”; or honors every man who wears glasses with “papa.” In the childhood of the race natural events were interpreted by means of analogy. The wind blowing through the trees made sounds much like the human voice; hence these noises were attributed to spirits. Primeval man was led to believe by analogy that everything which moved was alive. We may, therefore, think of our revered forbear as engaged in the undignified task of running after his shadow, or chasing a leaf around a stump. THE VALUE OF ANALOGY. Analogy being rich in its suggestions is the favored process of the scientist and inventor. Newton reasoned by analogy when he tentatively affirmed of the moon what he positively knew of the apple. Franklin’s reasoning was analogical when he discovered the identity of the electric spark and lightning. Because this form of induction so often leads to error and at best involves a degree of probability far below induction by analysis, some logicians are inclined to ignore its generalizations altogether. Others deem this a mistake because of these reasons: First. Analogy is serviceable to a high degree in suggesting hypotheses which may be advanced either for the purpose of explanation or verification. It has already been indicated that analogy is the common instrument used by the inventor and discoverer. Second. The principle of analogy, in reality, lies at the basis of classification; because in this, things are grouped according to their resemblances. Third. Analogical induction affords valuable training in originality and initiative. Amind which easily and naturally discerns analogies is “fertile in new ideas.” REQUIREMENTS OF A TRUE ANALOGY. It has been remarked that the certitude of an induction by simple enumeration depends upon the number of uncontradicted instances. In analogy the case is different as the process emphasizes the weight of the points of resemblance rather than the number. In substance the requirements of a logical analogy are three. First. The points of resemblance must be representative and not exceptional. For example: The argument that Mars is inhabited because it has two moons is of little worth, since we have no proof that moonshine is essential to life; this point of resemblance is not representative. On the other hand, if the basis of argument is the fact that Mars has an atmosphere, the conclusion carries some weight; as air seems to be essential to life. Second. The points of resemblance must outweigh the points of difference. That is, the ratio of probability must always be in favor of the resembling instances. Since it is not a matter of numbers but of weight, a numerical proportion like this would be misleading: Resemblances: Differences = 10:6. It is obvious that the six differences might more than outweigh the ten resemblances. The safer way, if it were possible, would be to attach a value to each point of resemblance or difference, and then express the proportion in terms of the sums of these values. Third. There must be no difference which is absolutely incompatible with the affirmation which we wish to prove. For example, the fact that the moon has no atmosphere renders nugatory any attempt to prove the habitability of the moon. 13. INDUCTION BY ANALYSIS.This, the third form of inductive research, is by far the most important. Simple enumeration, because it depends upon the number of observed instances, consumes much time; while we have already noted how easy it is Defined. We have learned that analysis is the process of separating a whole into its related parts. We thus define induction by analysis as the process of separating a whole into its parts with a view of deriving a generalization relative to the nature and causal connection of these parts. ILLUSTRATIONS: (1) Concerning the generalization that “all birds have wings,” it becomes possible to observe in detail the nature of the wings and advance the hypothesis that these wings are designed for aËrial navigation. This hypothesis may then be strengthened by observing that the entire structure of the bird is adapted to flying. (2) If it were possible to analyze the atmosphere, water, and soil of Mars, and should such analysis reveal a composition similar to that of the earth, it would illustrate well not only the method of analysis but also its superiority over the other methods of investigation. (3) The physician, in diagnosing a “case,” observes that the symptoms resemble those of typhoid; but to be positive of the truth of his diagnosis, he takes a blood test. Noting the resemblances is induction by analogy; but the blood test involves induction by analysis. Induction by analysis concerns hypothesis, observation, 14. PERFECT INDUCTION.As has been indicated under simple enumeration, a perfect induction is one in which the premises enumerate all the instances denoted by the conclusion. ILLUSTRATIONS: (1) A, B, C, D, and E are all Reactionaries, (All) The members of the committee are A, B, C, D, and E, ? (All) The members of the committee are Reactionaries. (2) John, James, Albert, and Peter all have perfect eyesight, John, James, Albert, and Peter are all the boys of my family, ? All the boys of my family have perfect eyesight. (3) The first, second, and third groups are up to grade, The first, second, and third groups include all of the children in my room, Hence all the children in my room are up to grade. Because the conclusion of a perfect induction gives nothing new—nothing but what is found in the premises, some claim that the process is practically valueless. From In the school room with classes addicted to careless, inaccurate work, to accept nothing but a perfectly induced generalization, when this is feasible, is a most valuable lesson. For example, the teacher may not accept the generalization that all of the “first class” cities of the U.S. are located on navigable waterways, until the pupils have investigated the waterway conditions of every city belonging to the class. On the other hand, there may be individual cases of “cocksureness” which need attention. The teacher can do little for the “know-it-all youngster” until he pricks the bubble of conceit. This may be accomplished (1) 2 + 2² + 41 = 47 (2) 3 + 3² + 41 = 53 (3) 4 + 4² + 41 = 61 (4) 7 + 7² + 41 = 97 (5) 10 + 10² + 41 = 151 A question or two will make apparent the fact that all the results are prime numbers, and then the generalization may be drawn; namely, X + X² + 41 = prime number. Now without warning, but under the assumption that you desire to test deductively the general formula, let X = 40. This gives (40 + 40² + 41) 1681, which is the square of 41 and is, therefore, not a prime number. 15. TRADUCTION.It may have been noted by the student that “perfect induction” is not induction at all according to the definition; viz.: Inductive reasoning is reasoning from less general premises to a more general conclusion. Referring to the first illustration of the previous section it is apparent Aside from the case of perfect induction there are other types which well illustrate traduction. These are: First. Reasoning from particular (or individuals) to particular (or individuals). ILLUSTRATION: Highland Street is the longest street in Jamaica, Highland Street is not so long as Broadway of New York City, ? The longest street of Jamaica is not so long as Broadway of New York City. Second. Reasoning from general to general. ILLUSTRATION: All growing things die, All living things are growing things, ? All living things die. It may be observed that all of the propositions in traduction are co-extensive “A’s” or “E’s”; hence all the All growing things are living things, All things that die are growing things, ? All things that die are living things. From the viewpoint of authenticity traduction is the most, and induction the least dependable; whereas the certitude of deductive reasoning lies somewhere between the two. On the other hand, when looked at from the ground of serviceableness the order is reversed, induction being the most useful form of inference and traduction the least. INDUCTIVE REASONING. (1) Inductive and Deductive Reasoning Distinguished. (2) The “Inductive Hazard.” Essential in world’s progress. Cultivated and regulated in school. (3) Complexity of the Problem of Induction. (4) Various Conceptions of Induction. Quotations from prominent authorities. (5) Induction and Deduction Contiguous Processes. (6) Induction an Assumption. A mode of inference; Amethod. (7) Universal Causation. Law stated and illustrated. Conditions all induction. (8) Uniformity of Nature. Defined and illustrated. Conditions all induction. Empirical. (9) Inductive Assumptions Justified. (10) Three Forms of Inductive Research. (1) Enumeration (2)Analogy (3)Analysis. Illustrated. Conditions determine form followed. (11) Induction by Simple Enumeration. Defined and illustrated. Outcome threefold—these illustrated. (12) Induction by Analogy. Two conceptions. Analogy by type or example. Illustrations representative. Error of analogy. Suggestiveness of analogy. Value of analogy. Requirements of a true analogy. Three. (13) Induction by Analysis. Importance. Defined and illustrated. (14) Perfect Induction. Defined and illustrated. Its use. Method of Socrates. (15) Traduction. Defined and illustrated. Three methods compared. 17. SUMMARY.(1) Reasoning is the process of deriving a judgment from two antecedent judgments. The syllogism is a common form of expressing the process of reasoning. Inductive reasoning is reasoning from less general premises to a more general conclusion. Deductive reasoning is reasoning from more general premises to a less general conclusion. The inductive syllogism is not supposed to conform to the canons of the deductive syllogism. (2) Positing in the conclusion more than is indicated in the premises involves what is known as the “inductive hazard.” The inductive hazard which is another expression for the spirit of discovery, should be fostered in the school room since it has been one of the great forces in human progress; but this venturesome spirit must be regulated by rules, principles, and systematic procedure, or low ideals of recklessness and inaccuracy will result. (3) The problem of induction is more complex than that of deduction; because the former is a comparatively new subject, and also is more closely related to the activities of life. (4) The opinion relative to the exact nature of induction, though varied, may be summed up in the thought of its being the process which leads to general truths, derived from the observation of individual facts. (5) Induction and deduction are contiguous processes which go to make up the more general process of thinking. Where induction ceases, deduction naturally commences; induction discovers new knowledge, deduction clarifies it. (6) Induction as a general process may be treated as a mode of inference or as a method. In either case the conclusion comprehends more than is contained in the premises. Since no imperfect induction is absolutely free from doubt, on what ground are we justified in making any inductive assumptions? The answer follows: (7 and 8) “Nothing can occur without a cause and every cause has its effect,” is the law of universal causation; while the law of the uniformity of nature is “the same antecedents are universally followed by the same consequents.” These two laws justify inductive assumptions, and, in a sense, condition all thinking. (9) Uniformity of nature gives man confidence, while universal causation arouses his curiosity. With these two weapons he is willing to “march into the unknown.” (10) As the process of universalizing individual experiences, induction assumes the three forms of simple enumeration, analogy and analysis. The form adopted is not always elective but is controlled largely by the exigency of the case. Some topics lend themselves to all three modes. (11) Induction by simple enumeration consists in observing many instances which exemplify the uniformity under consideration. (12) Induction by analogy assumes that if two (or more) things resemble each other in certain respects, they belong to the same type, and, therefore, any fact known of the one, may be affirmed of the other. A most common form of analogy is reasoning by type or example. In this it is assumed that if two or more things are of the same type, they resemble each in every essential property. The type must be truly representative. Asecond form of analogy is reasoning by marks of resemblance. This second form often leads to egregious error. Analogy is especially valuable in suggesting hypotheses and in giving training in originality and initiative. A true analogy demands that the points of resemblance be representative; that they outweigh the points of difference, and that no disagreement be incompatible. (13) Induction by analysis is the process of dividing a whole into its parts with a view of deriving a generalization relative to the nature and causal connection of these parts. Induction by analysis makes use of the hypothesis, of observation and experiment, including Mill’s five methods. (14) A perfect induction is one in which the premises enumerate all of the instances denoted by the conclusion. It is serviceable in inspiring care and accuracy in the establishment of generalizations. (15) Traduction is the process of reasoning to a conclusion which is neither less general nor more general than the premises. Traduction includes reasoning from particular to particular or from general to general. Perfect induction is in reality a form of traduction. Induction, though the most useful form of inference, is the most untrustworthy; whereas traduction is just the reverse of this. 18. REVIEW QUESTIONS.(1) Define and illustrate reasoning. (2) Distinguish by definition and illustration between inductive and deductive reasoning. (3) Explain the “inductive hazard” and show its use to man. (4) “For twenty centuries Aristotle’s Deductive Logic was the logician’s bible.” Explain this. (5) Show that induction and deduction are contiguous processes. (6) Distinguish between induction as a mode of inference and induction as a method. (7) State and explain the law of universal causation. Illustrate fully. (8) Make evident that a cause may involve many antecedents. (9) State and explain by illustration the law of uniformity of nature. (10) Verify by illustration the notion that the “fact of causation” conditions all induction. (11) Which of the two laws is empirical, “causation” or “uniformity”? Why? (12) Show that induction is a form of thinking. (13) Why should the law of uniformity of nature convince man that nature is honest? Illustrate. (14) Show that the law of universal causation stirs the spirit of discovery. (15) Name and illustrate the three forms of induction. (16) Why is it that the tendencies of the investigator often determine the inductive form which he adopts? (17) Explain by illustration the three-fold outcome of induction by simple enumeration. (18) Selecting some class room experience, illustrate analogy by example or type. (19) Define and exemplify types as used in logic. (20) Remark upon the errors incident to analogy. (21) Summarize the advantages which induction by analogy offers. (22) State and exemplify the requirements of true analogies. (23) Indicate the superiority of induction by analysis over the other two forms. Illustrate. (24) Define and illustrate perfect induction. (25) Under what circumstances is perfect induction justified? (26) Define and illustrate traduction. (27) Indicate the various forms of traduction. 19. QUESTIONS FOR ORIGINAL THOUGHT AND INVESTIGATION.(1) Show the connection between illicit minor and the “inductive hazard.” (2) Show by illustration that time tends to universalize truth. (3) “Induction and not deduction is the natural method of the child mind.” Prove the correctness of this statement. (4) “Induction is the process of inference by which we get at general truths from particular facts or cases.” Prove that this is not strictly correct according to definition. (5) As related to establishing general truths, what are the special functions of induction and deduction? (6) Show that an inductive inference must of necessity be more or less uncertain. (7) Is there any distinction between the laws of universal causation and sufficient reason? Hyslop’s Elements of Logic, page329. (8) Show that universal causation and uniformity of nature are complementary laws. Hyslop, p.330. (9) Relate the “fact of causation” to the laws of thought. (10) Distinguish between empirical and “a priori” laws. (11) When Harvey discovered the circulation of the blood, what form of induction did he use? (12) What form of reasoning did Columbus follow in proving that the earth is spherical? (13) “It is said that the greatness of Darwin was due largely to his habit of never ignoring an exception.” Justify by illustration the truth of this assertion. (14) In analogical reasoning by example, under what conditions would one illustration be as convincing as many? (15) “Considering the similarities and differences, the weight of the argument favors Mars’ habitability.” Suppose the proportion of probability were something like this—Resemblances: Differences = 8:7; wherein might the conclusion be erroneous? (16) Mention a mark or characteristic which would make the habitability of Mars incompatible? (17) Select a topic for investigation which is peculiarly adapted to enumeration; to analogy; to analysis. (18) “The uniformities we expect to find in the world take two main aspects, one of which is indicated by the term thing and the other by the term circumstance.” Aikin’s Principles of Logic, 1905; p.233. In the light of the two fundamental laws of universal causation and uniformity of nature explain and illustrate the quotation. (19) Explain the principle of teleology as related to analogy. Hibben, 1908; p.317. |