TABLE OF CONTENTS.

Previous
590-h@59590-h-12.htm.html#sect125" class="pginternal">125.
The use of Diagrams in Logic 156
126. Euler’s Diagrams 157
127. Lambert’s Diagrams 163
128. Dr Venn’s Diagrams 166
129. Expression of the possible relations between any two classes by means of the propositional forms A, E, I, O 168
130. Euler’s diagrams and the class-relations between S, not-S, P, not-P 170
131. Lambert’s diagrams and the class-relations between S, not-S, P, not-P 174
132 to 134. Exercises 176
xv
CHAPTER VI.
PROPOSITIONS IN EXTENSION AND IN INTENSION.
135. Fourfold Implication of Propositions in Connotation and Denotation 177
(1) Subject in denotation, predicate in connotation 179
(2) Subject in denotation, predicate in denotation 181
(3) Subject in connotation, predicate in connotation 184
(4) Subject in connotation, predicate in denotation 186
136. The Reading of Propositions in Comprehension 187
CHAPTER VII.
LOGICAL EQUATIONS AND THE QUANTIFICATION OF THE PREDICATE.
137. The employment of the symbol of Equality in Logic 189
138. Types of Logical Equations 191
139. The expression of Propositions as Equations 194
140. The eight propositional forms resulting from the explicit Quantification of the Predicate 195
141. Sir William Hamilton’s fundamental Postulate of Logic 195
142. Advantages claimed for the Quantification of the Predicate 196
143. Objections urged against the Quantification of the Predicate 197
144. The meaning to be attached to the word some in the eight propositional forms recognised by Sir William Hamilton 199
145. The use of some in the sense of some only 202
146. The interpretation of the eight Hamiltonian forms of proposition, some being used in its ordinary logical sense 203
147. The propositions U and Y 264. Further discussion of the process of Indirect Reduction 331
265. The Antilogism 332
266. Equivalence of the Moods of the first three Figures shewn by the Method of Indirect Reduction 333
267. The Moods of Figure 4 in their relation to one another 334
268. Equivalence of the Special Rules of the First Three Figures 335
269. Scheme of the Valid Moods of Figure 1 336
270. Scheme of the Valid Moods of Figure 2 336
271. Scheme of the Valid Moods of Figure 3 337
272. Dictum for Figure 4 338
273 to 287. Exercises 339
CHAPTER IV.
THE DIAGRAMMATIC REPRESENTATION OF SYLLOGISMS.
288. Euler’s diagrams and syllogistic reasonings 341
289. Lambert’s diagrams and syllogistic reasonings 344
290. Dr Venn’s diagrams and syllogistic reasonings 345
291 to 300. Exercises 347
CHAPTER V.
CONDITIONAL AND HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS.
301. The Conditional Syllogism, the Hypothetical Syllogism, and the Hypothetico-Categorical Syllogism 348
302. Distinctions of Mood and Figure in the case of Conditional and Hypothetical Syllogisms 349
303. Fallacies in Hypothetical Syllogisms 350
304. The Reduction of Conditional and Hypothetical Syllogisms 351
xix
305. The Moods of the Mixed Hypothetical Syllogism 352
306. Fallacies in Mixed Hypothetical Syllogisms 353
307. The Reduction of Mixed Hypothetical Syllogisms 354
308. Is the reasoning contained in the mixed hypothetical syllogism mediate or immediate? 354
309 to 315. Exercises 358
CHAPTER VI.
DISJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISMS.
xxiv

REFERENCE LIST OF INITIAL LETTERS SHEWING THE AUTHORSHIP OR SOURCE OF QUESTIONS AND PROBLEMS.

  • B = Professor J. I. Beare, Trinity College, Dublin;
  • C = University of Cambridge;
  • J = Mr W. E. Johnson, King’s College, Cambridge;
  • K = Dr J. N. Keynes, Pembroke College, Cambridge;
  • L = University of London;
  • M = University of Melbourne;
  • N = Professor J. S. Nicholson, University of Edinburgh;
  • O = University of Oxford;
  • O’S = Mr C. A. O’Sullivan, Trinity College, Dublin;
  • R = the late Professor G. Croom Robertson;
  • RR = Mr R. A. P. Rogers, Trinity College, Dublin;
  • T = Dr F. A. Tarleton, Trinity College, Dublin;
  • V = Dr J. Venn, Gonville and Caius College, Cambridge;
  • W = Professor J. Ward, Trinity College, Cambridge.

Note. A few problems have been selected from the published writings of Boole, De Morgan, Jevons, Solly, Venn, and Whately, from the Port Royal Logic, and from the Johns Hopkins Studies in Logic. In these cases the source of the problem is appended in full.

STUDIES AND EXERCISES IN FORMAL LOGIC.

INTRODUCTION.

1. The General Character of Logic.—Logic may be defined as the science which investigates the general principles of valid thought. Its object is to discuss the characteristics of judgments, regarded not as psychological phenomena but as expressing our knowledge and beliefs; and, in particular, it seeks to determine the conditions under which we are justified in passing from given judgments to other judgments that follow from them.

As thus defined, logic has in view an ideal; it is concerned fundamentally with how we ought to think, and only indirectly and as a means to an end with how we actually think. It may accordingly be described as a normative or regulative science. This character it possesses in common with ethics and aesthetics. These three branches of knowledge—all of them based on psychology—form a unique trio, to be distinguished from positive sciences on the one hand, and from practical arts on the other. It may be said roughly that they are concerned with the ideal in the domains of thought, action, and feeling respectively. Logic seeks to determine the general principles of valid thought, ethics the general principles of right conduct, aesthetics the general principles of correct taste.

2. Formal Logic.—As regards the scope of logic, one of the principal questions ordinarily raised is whether the science is formal or material, subjective or objective, concerned with 2 thoughts or with things. It is usual to say that logic is formal, in so far as it is concerned merely with the form of thought, that is, with our manner of thinking irrespective of the particular objects about which we are thinking; and that it is material, in so far as it regards as fundamental the objective reference of our thought, and recognises as of essential importance the differences existing in the objects themselves about which we think.

Logic is certainly formal, or at any rate non-material, in the sense that it cannot guarantee the actual objective or material truth of any particular conclusions. Moreover any valid reasoning whatsoever must conform to some definite type, or—in other words—must be reducible to some determinate form; and one of the main objects of logic is by abstraction to discover what are the various types or forms to which all valid reasoning may be reduced.

But, on the other hand, it is essential that logic should recognise an objective reference in every judgment, that is, a reference outside the state of mind which constitutes the judgment itself: apart from this, as we shall endeavour to shew in more detail later on, the true nature of judgment cannot be understood. It is, moreover, possible for logic to examine and formulate certain general conditions which must be satisfied if our thoughts and judgments are to have objective validity; and the science may recognise and discuss certain general presuppositions relating to external nature which are involved in passing from the particular facts of observation to general laws.

Logic fully treated has then both a formal and a material side. The question may indeed be raised whether the distinction between form and matter is not a relative, rather than an absolute, distinction. All sciences are in a sense formal, since they abstract to some extent from the matter of thought. Thus physics abstracts in the main from the chemical properties of bodies, while geometry abstracts also from their physical properties, considering their figure only. In this way we become more and more formal as we become more and more general; and logic may be said to be more abstract, more 3 general, more formal, than any other science, except perhaps pure mathematics.

It is to be added that, within the domain of logic itself, the answer to the question whether two given propositions have or have not the same form may depend upon the particular system of propositions in connexion with which they are considered. Thus, if we carry our analysis no further than is usual in ordinary formal logic, the two propositions, Every angle in a semi-circle is equal to a right angle, Any two sides of a triangle are together greater than the third side, may be considered to be identical in form. Each is universal, and each is affirmative; they differ only in matter. But it will be found that in the logic of relatives, to which further reference will subsequently be made, the two propositions (one expressing an equality and the other an inequality) may be regarded as differing in form as well as in matter; and, moreover, that the difference between them in form is capable of being symbolically expressed.

The difficulty of assigning a distinctive scope to formal logic par excellence is increased by the fact that certain problems falling naturally into the domain of material logic—for example, the inductive methods—admit up to a certain point of a purely formal treatment.

It is not possible then to draw a hard and fast line and to say that a certain determinate portion of logic is formal, and that the rest is not formal. We must content ourselves with the statement that when we speak of formal logic in a distinctive sense we mean the most abstract parts of the science, in which no presuppositions are made relating to external nature, and in which—beyond the recognition of the necessary objective reference contained in all judgments—there is an abstraction from the matter of thought. Because they are so abstract, the problems of formal logic as thus conceived admit usually of symbolic treatment; and it is with problems admitting of such treatment that we shall more particularly concern ourselves in the following pages.

3. Logic and Language.—Some logicians, in their treatment of the problems of formal logic, endeavour to abstract not 4 merely from the matter of thought but also from the language which is the instrument of thought. This method of treatment is not adopted in the following pages. In order to justify the adoption of the alternative method, it is not necessary to maintain that thought is altogether impossible without language. It is enough that all thought-processes of any degree of complexity are as a matter of fact carried on by the aid of language, and that thought-products are normally expressed in language. That language is in this sense the universal instrument of thought will not be denied; and it seems a fair corollary that the principles by which valid thought is regulated, and more especially the application of these principles to the criticism of thought-products, cannot be adequately discussed, unless account is taken of the way in which this instrument actually performs its functions.

Language is full of ambiguities, and it is impossible to proceed far with the problems with which logic is concerned until a precise interpretation has been placed upon certain forms of words as representing thought. In ordinary discourse, to take a simple example, the word some may or may not be used in a sense in which it is exclusive of all ; it may be understood to mean not-all as well as not-none, or its full meaning may be taken to be not-none. The logician must decide in which of these senses the word is to be understood in any given scheme of propositional forms. Now, if thought were considered exclusively in itself, such a question as this could not arise; it has to do with the expression of thought in language. The fact that such questions do arise and cannot help arising shews that actually to eliminate all consideration of language from logic is an impossibility. A not infrequent result of attempting to rise above mere considerations of language is needless prolixity and dogmatism in regard to what are really verbal questions, though they are not recognised as such.

The method of treating logic here advocated is sometimes called nominalist, and the opposed method conceptualist. A word or two of explanation is, however, desirable in order that this use of terms may not prove misleading. Nominalism and conceptualism usually denote certain doctrines concerning the 5 nature of general notions. Nominalism is understood to involve the assertion that generality belongs to language alone and that there is nothing general in thought. But a so-called nominalist treatment of logic does not involve this. It involves no more than a clear recognition of the importance of language as the instrument of thought; and this is a circumstance upon which modern advocates of conceptualism have themselves insisted.

It is perhaps necessary to add that on the view here taken logic in no way becomes a mere branch of grammar, nor does it cease to have a place amongst the mental sciences. Whatever may be the aid derived from language, it remains true that the validity of formal reasonings depends ultimately on laws of thought. Formal logic is, therefore, still concerned primarily with thought, and only secondarily with language as the instrument of thought.

In our subsequent discussion of the relation of terms to concepts, and of propositions to judgments, we shall return to a consideration of the question raised in this section.2

2 See sections 7 and 46.

4. Logic and Psychology.—Since processes of reasoning are mental processes depending upon the constitution of our minds, they fall within the cognizance of psychology as well as of logic. But laws of reasoning are regarded from different points of view by these two sciences. Psychology deals with such laws in the sense of uniformities, that is, as laws in accordance with which men are found by experience normally to think and reason. Logic, on the other hand, deals with laws of reasoning as regulative and authoritative, as affording criteria by the aid of which valid and invalid reasonings may be discriminated, and as determining the formal relations in which different products of thought stand to one another.

Looking at the relations between logic and psychology from a slightly different standpoint, we observe that while the latter is concerned with the actual, the former is concerned with the ideal. Logic does not, like psychology, treat of all the ways in which men actually reach conclusions, or of all the various modes in which, through the association of ideas or otherwise, one belief actually generates another. It is concerned with 6 reasonings only as regards their cogency, and with the dependence of one judgment upon another only in so far as it is a dependence in respect of proof.

There are various other ways in which the contrast between the two sciences may be expressed. We may, for example, say that psychology is concerned with thought-processes, logic with thought-products; or that psychology is concerned with the origin of our beliefs, logic with their validity.

Logic has thus a unique character of its own, and is not a mere branch of psychology. Psychological and logical discussions are no doubt apt to overlap one another at certain points, in connexion, for example, with theories of conception and judgment. In the following pages, however, the psychological side of logic is comparatively little touched upon. The metaphysical questions also to which logic tends to give rise are as far as possible avoided.

5. The Utility of Logic.—We have seen that logic has in view an ideal and treats of what ought to be. Its object is, however, to investigate general principles, and it puts forward no claim to be a practical art. Its utility is accordingly not to be measured by any direct help that it may afford towards the attainment of particular scientific truths. No doubt the procedure in all sciences is subject to the general principles formulated by logic; but, in details, the weighing of evidence will often be better performed by the judgment of the expert than by any formal or systematic observance of logical rules.

It is important to bear in mind that, in the study of logic, our immediate aim is the scientific investigation of general principles recognised as authoritative in relation to thought-products, not the formulation of a system of rules and precepts. It may be said that the art of dealing with particular concrete arguments, with the object of determining their validity, is related to the science of logic in the same way as the art of casuistry (that is, the art of deciding what it is right to do in particular concrete circumstances) is related to the science of ethics. Moreover, just as in the art of casuistry we meet with problems which are elusive and difficult to decide because in the concrete they cannot be brought exactly under the abstract 7 formulae of ethical science, so in the art of detecting fallacies we meet with arguments which cannot easily be brought under the abstract formulae of logical science. As it would be a mistake to subordinate ethics to the treatment of casuistical questions, so it would be a mistake to mould the science of logic with constant reference to concrete arguments which, either because of the ambiguity of the terms employed, or because of the uncertain bearing of the context in which they occur, elude any attempt to reduce them to a form to which general principles are directly applicable.

Wherein then consists the utility of logic? In answer to this question, it may be observed primarily that if logic determines truly the principles of valid thought, then its study is of value simply in that it adds to our knowledge. To justify the study of logic it is, as Mansel has observed, sufficient to shew that what it teaches is true, and that by its aid we advance in the knowledge of ourselves and of our capacities.

To this it must be added (in qualification of what has been said previously) that, while logic is not to be regarded as an art of attaining truth, it still does possess utility as propaedeutic to other studies and independently of the addition that it makes to our knowledge. Fallacious arguments can no doubt usually be recognised as such by an acute intellect apart from any logical study; and, as we have seen, it is not the primary function of logic to deal with particular concrete arguments. At the same time, it is only by the aid of logic that we can analyse a reasoning, explain precisely why a fallacious argument is faulty, and give the fallacy a name. In other words, while logic is not to be identified with the criticism of particular concrete arguments, such criticism when systematically undertaken must be based on logic.

Greater, however, than the indirect value of logic in its subsequent application to the examination of particular reasonings is its value as a general intellectual discipline. The study of logic cultivates the power of abstract thought; and it is not too much to say that, when undertaken with thoroughness, it affords a unique mental training.

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                           

Clyx.com


Top of Page
Top of Page