A Picture of Our Universe. CHAPTER I.

Previous

It seems to me that the subject of higher space is becoming felt as serious, and fraught with much that is of the deepest interest, not only as a scientific problem, but in other ways also.

It seems also that when we commence to feel the seriousness of any subject we partly lose our faculty of dealing with it. The intellect seems to be overweighted somehow, and clogged. Perhaps the suppositions we make seem to us of too great importance, and we are not willing enough to let them go, fearing to lose the thing itself if we lose our hold of the means by which we have first apprehended it.

But whatever may be the cause, it does seem undoubtedly the fact that the mind works more clearly and more freely on subjects which are of slight importance.

And I propose, that without ignoring the real importance of the subject about which we are treating, we should cast aside any tension from our minds, and look at it in a light and easy manner.

With this object in view let us contemplate a certain story which bears on our problem.

It is said that once in a certain region of Ireland there took place a curious contest. For in Kilkenny there were two cats so alike in size, vigour, determination, and prowess, that, fighting, they so clawed, scratched, bit, and finally devoured each other, that nothing was left of either of them save the tail.

Now, on reflecting on this story, it becomes obvious that it originated when looking-glasses were first imported into Ireland from Italy. For when an Irishman sees for the first time anything new, he always describes it in an unexpected and yet genial and interesting manner. Moreover, we all know what contentious fellows they are, and how all their thoughts run on fighting. And I think if we put this problem to ourselves, how by bringing in fighting to describe a looking-glass, we shall see that the story of the Kilkenny cats is the only possible solution. For consider evidently how it arose. Depositing his favourite shillaly in a corner, the massively-built Irishman, to whom the possession was a novelty, saw reflected in his looking-glass the image of his favourite cat. With a scrutinizing eye he compared the two. Point for point they were like. “Begorra if I know which of the two would win!” he ejaculates. The combat becomes real to him, and the story of the Kilkenny cats is made.

Now, to our more sober mind, it is obvious that two cats—two real material things—could not mutually annihilate each other to such an extent. But it is perfectly possible to make a model of the Kilkenny cats—to see them fight, and to mark the issue.

And I propose to symbolize or represent the Kilkenny cat by a twist. Take a pencil, and round it twist a strip of paper—a flat spill will do. Now, having fastened the ends on to the pencil by two pins, so that it will not untwist, hold the paper thus twisted on the pencil at right angles to the surface of a looking-glass: and in the looking-glass you will see its image. In Diagram I., M represents the mirror, and on the left hand is shown the twist, on the right hand the image twist. Now take another pencil and another piece of paper, and make a model of what you see in the glass. You will be able to twist this second piece of paper in a spiral round this second pencil so that it is an exact copy of what you see in the glass. Now put the two pencils together end to end, as they would be if the first pencil were to approach the glass until it touched it, meeting its image: you have the real copy of the image instead of the image itself. Now pin together the two ends of the pieces of paper, which are near together, and you have your two Kilkenny cats ready for the fray. To make them fight (remember that the twists—not the paper itself, but the paper twisted—represent the cat), hold firmly and pull the other ends (the tail ends, so to speak), so as to let each twist exercise its nature on the other.

You will see that the two twists mutually annihilate each other. Without your unwrapping the paper the twists both go, and nothing is left of them.

Diagram I.

Now the image of the twist as a real thing was made by us. It did not exist in nature other than as a mere appearance.

But I want you to imagine this process of producing a real image as somehow existing. I want you to lay aside for the present the question of how it could be done, and to conceive twists and image twists.

This is the mechanical conception I wish you to adopt—there are such things as twists. Suppose by some means to every twist there is produced its image twist. These two, the twist and its image, may exist separately; but suppose that whenever a twist is produced its image twist is also produced, and that these two when put together annihilate each other.

With this conception let us explore the domain of those actions which are called electrical.

When a glass rod is rubbed with silk it becomes excited, its state is different. It manifests many properties, such as that of attracting light bodies, giving off a glow of light, &c. The silk also with which it was rubbed manifests similar properties. It also attracts light bodies, appears to glow in the dark, &c.

And yet there is a difference between the state of excitement of the glass and of the silk. The electricity which is in them is of different kinds. And if the electricity of the silk and of the glass be brought together, all electrical effect disappears; they become glass and silk in an ordinary condition.

It may seem strange that, if this is so, they should become electrified when rubbed together. Yet this is the case, and must be taken as a fact. It seems to depend partly on the circumstance that glass and silk are not what is called conductors. In a conductor, if one part receives electricity, this electricity at once runs over the whole of the conductor, whether it be an inch long or many feet. And if any part of the conductor be touched by another conductor which is in contact with the earth, every trace of electricity leaves the conductor, flowing, as it were, freely out of it.

Now both glass and silk do not let the electricity run from them so easily. To discharge a glass rod it has practically to be touched in every part. Thus, when by the rubbing with silk electricity is produced on it, it is conceivable that this electricity should be kept to a certain extent, and not combined immediately with the electricity on the silk.

Besides, the same cause—the friction which produced the electricity on the glass, and the other kind of electricity on the silk—would probably prevent their combination as long as it was applied.

Now let us suppose that the electrical charge which the glass has consists in this.

Let us suppose that the particles of the glass on the surface of it are twisted, strained out of their natural position, and twisted.

Let us also suppose that the particles of the silk are twisted too, but let them have the image twist.

Now these two twists, the glass twist and the silk twist, its image, when brought together, will run down. In unwinding each other they will give off a certain amount of energy, which will manifest itself as a spark, make a crackling sound, and so on. But when they unwind each other there is no more tension of the particles.

This does not explain in the least why the glass particles should receive a twist in one direction, the silk particles a twist of the image kind.

But instead of inquiring into this, it is best to see if this supposition is in accordance with other known facts of electrical action; because, if it is not, we may dismiss it more easily than we could if we had to test it with regard to the very inaccessible question of why some bodies, when rubbed, get electrified in one way, others in another.

When the glass and silk are near together the twist on the glass and that on the silk are related to each other as twist and image twist, and there is no action on surrounding bodies from either of them, as they, so to speak, satisfy each other.

But when the glass rod and the silk are moved apart, and brought near other objects, then each of them calls up on those objects near which it is brought a twist of the kind which is the image of its own twist.

If the glass rod is brought near a mass of metal, which we will call a conductor, the following effect is observed:—The part of the conductor near the glass rod becomes charged with electricity of the silk kind; the part of the conductor away from the rod becomes charged with electricity of the glass kind.

Now let us bring into play the supposition which we made before.

Let us suppose that there is some process in nature which, when there is a twist, makes a real image of that twist come into being. If we assume this process, we see that, opposite to the silk, on whatever objects are near it, will be a twist of the glass kind, and opposite the rod will be a twist of the silk kind. That is to say, that on the conductor there will be a twist of the silk kind when the glass rod is brought near it.

But there is nothing to make the particles of the conductor twist as a whole. The glass rod is not supposed to touch the conductor—it is simply brought near it, and no actual communication takes place between them. No force is actually applied to it, nor electricity communicated to it. Hence, on the whole, the particles of the conductor will not be twisted. That is to say, since there is a twist of the glass kind on one end, there will be at the other end a twist of the image kind—that is, of the silk kind. And these two twists are like the two twists on the pencil—if allowed to run together they will run each other out. So if the conductor were removed from the neighbourhood of the glass rod it would be found to be no different from what it was at first. It would not be “charged.”

Now this is what actually happens.

Thus we have, firstly, a glass rod with its twist; secondly, a mass of metal with two twists on it—one near the glass rod, and of the image kind; the other at the other end of the mass of metal, and related to the original twist in the following way. It is the image of its image.

Now it will be found by using a mirror that the image of the image of a twist is the twist itself.

Hence on the other end of the conductor there is a twist of the same kind as that on the glass rod.

And it is obvious that the rod, with its twist, is connected with the twist on the conductor nearest to it, and the twist on the other end of the conductor will, by the same arbitrary process which we have assumed as real, call up a twist, the image of itself, on any object near it.

If it is touched by the object with this contrary twist the two will run together, and the conductor will, if it is left free, have only one twist—the silk kind, which has come up opposite the rod.

If now the rod be moved away, the conductor will be twisted as a whole; that is, all the particles of which it is composed will be slightly twisted with a twist of the silk kind.

In this state it is said to be charged.

Thus the assumption which we have made, that there is some process in nature in virtue of which, opposite to any twist, its image twist is produced as a real thing—this assumption is in harmony with the laws of induction.

Instead of working with a glass rod it is more convenient to use a metal rod. Suppose we take a poker and attach a handle of sealing wax to its middle. See A B below. This will be easily imagined, and its two ends, the handle and the black end, will be easily retained in the mind.

If now electricity be communicated from the glass rod to the poker by touching the two together, what happens is this: The particles of the glass being twisted communicate their twist to the particles of the poker. The twist on the poker is of the same kind as the twist on the glass rod, and the amount of twisting which the glass particles had is divided between the glass rod and the poker. The use of the sealing-wax handle is to keep the twist from communicating itself to the body of the person holding it, and, through him, to the earth. It is found that certain bodies, “non-conductors,” will not communicate the twist and convey it along; whereas metallic bodies, and conductors generally, will communicate this twist at once to great distances.

We will suppose that a metallic body consists of particles so arranged together that it easily acts as a set of minute threads or chains of particles which will twist, each thread or chain twisting as a whole. Thus the conception which should be formed of a metallic body conducting electricity along it is this:—Conceive a bundle of very fine but very rigid wires, each wire twisting separately but with the same kind of twist as all the others, and each, as it twists, rotating amongst its fellow threads. If we have a metal rod we can twist it between the finger and thumb. This is not the kind of twist we suppose, but that each separate string of particles is thus twisted, so that each set twisting remains in the same part of the metal rod—but is turning round in its fixed position. This is a body conveying an electric current. If the current will not pass, the set of minute wires must be conceived as held at the far end, and given a twist, starting from the point where the electricity is communicated. Now if a conductor is thus charged and left, it is found that it retains its charge; to be discharged it must be touched with another conductor. Hence this twist of minute threads differs from a twist of a wire in that the threads cannot untwist of themselves unless other threads come into contact with them to which they can impart the twist. That this should be the case may depend on the fact that the twisting strings are strings of molecules, and the ends of them would thus be connected with other molecules with something of the same tenacity as that with which the strings themselves cohere together, and are unable to unlock themselves from these insulating or untwisting molecules.

Let us consider the state due to these twisting strings of particles.

Place two pennies lying on the table before you, and suppose them to be the sections in which two strings of a conductor are cut across, so that you are looking at two particles, represented by the pennies in the interior of a conductor; the strings, of which the pennies are sections, come up towards your eye. Now twist the two pennies each in the same direction—say that of the hands of a watch. From the outer edges you can take the motion off; the edges are moving in the same direction. But where the two pennies meet you will see that the edge of each is going in a contrary direction to the other. And if one penny tends to move an object in one way the other tends to move it in the contrary direction. Hence these motions tend to neutralize each other in the interior of a conducting wire.

Having now formed a conception of the state of the particles in an electrified poker, suppose another poker likewise held by an insulating handle is brought near the first. Let the pokers be so arranged that the handles both point one way, the black ends another way, and let the second poker be in the same line as the first, with its handle towards the black end of the first.

Now the first poker is charged, it contains electricity, its particles are twisted. What effect will it have on the second poker?

It is found that the second poker undergoes a certain change, but when it is removed to a distance from the first poker all trace of this change disappears.

On the end nearest the first poker—on the handle—is found silk electricity; on the end furthest from the first poker—on the black end—is found glass electricity.

A BC D
+ +- +

Let A B be one poker, the + representing the charge of glass electricity. Let C D represent the other poker, the - representing the induced silk electricity, the + the glass electricity in it.

Let A be the handle of the first, B its black end. Let C be the handle of the second, and D its black end. To explain this let us bring in our imaginary principle. Let us suppose that when a charged body is brought near an uncharged body, but is separated from it by some medium through which electricity cannot pass—let us suppose that by some agency the twist in the charged body calls up an image twist in the body opposite it. Thus, due to the twist in the first poker there will be an image twist in the handle part of the second poker.

But the strings of particles in the second poker are not twisted as a whole; they are twisted in such a way that if they are removed from the first poker, the twist, whatever it be, disappears.

Now this would obviously be effected if we suppose the same thing to go on in the second poker as took place between the first poker and the second. Let the twist in the handle end C of the second poker be accompanied by the production of an image twist in the black end D. And let us take this as a fair account of our observations. If a body, which as a whole does not undergo a twist, has one part of it twisted, then there will be the image twist in the other part of it. I say that the poker as a whole is not twisted, and all that this means is that if it be removed from the electrical influence it is found to be not charged; and the idea which we may form is this: the strings of particles are twisted like the two strips of paper round the pencil; they are twisted so that they will exactly unwind if left alone.

Now of course all these suppositions are merely provisional, and must be dismissed unless seen to be mechanically possible; but for the present we are trying to see if our assumption will fit in with facts. And our assumption is that there is in nature a power which amongst the molecules produces that as a real thing which in our larger mode of existence only occurs as a simulacrum and appearance. Our looking-glass images are not real, but we suppose that real images are produced amongst the molecules.[3]

We have seen that if we make a certain supposition as to the calling up of an image twist by a twist of molecular matter, then the main facts of electricity are capable of an explanation, which, involving merely the motion of ordinary matter, is far preferable to the idea of there being a mysterious fluid, and more in harmony with our present ideas of electricity.

And yet it is impossible to retain this supposition unless a clear mechanical explanation can be given of how a real image of itself can be called up by the twist which we suppose electricity to be.

We can by intelligent agency produce a twist which is the real image of a given twist. But it would be absurd to suppose amongst the molecules an agency which, acting with prescribed aim, gave in that domain those real simulacra, those evident images, those phantoms with which we in our larger world of masses are for ever mocked.

And yet it would be curious if such an hypothesis were to claim a recognized position in our mental apparatus with which we think about nature.

For in that molecular world, if we imagine it to ourselves, there would be a curious state.

If we consider a twist and its image, they are but the simplest and most rudimentary type of an organism. What holds good of a twist and its image twist would hold good of a more complicated arrangement also. If a bit of structure apparently very unlike a twist, and with manifold parts and differences in it—if such a structure were to meet its image structure, each of them would instantly unwind the other, and what was before a complex and compound whole, opposite to an image of itself, would at once be resolved into a string of formless particles. A flash, a blaze, and all would be over.

To realize what this would mean we must conceive that in our world there were to be for each man somewhere a counter-man, a presentment of himself, a real counterfeit, outwardly fashioned like himself, but with his right hand opposite his original’s right hand. Exactly like the image of the man in a mirror.

And then when the man and his counterfeit met, a sudden whirl, a blaze, a little steam, and the two human beings, having mutually unwound each other, leave nothing but a residuum of formless particles.

CHAPTER II.

What physical explanation is possible of this production of a real image?

First of all we may note that the production of a real image of any disturbance is one of the commonest phenomena.

If a piece of indiarubber lying on the table be pressed downwards with the finger it will move up when the finger is removed. The yielding and the resuming its original form are movement and image movement.

If the disturbance is simply a displacement in one line, then, if the medium in which this displacement is produced is not permanently displaced, but on the whole maintains its equilibrium, there invariably accompanies any displacement its image displacement.

Moreover, to take the simple example of a wave propagated through water—the particles of the water on the whole move about a mean position; they are not displaced permanently in any one direction; and, taking the distance from the crest to the hollow of a wave, then from the hollow to the next crest, is the real image of the first part. Thus in the complete movement in the wave measured from crest to crest, there is displacement and its real image.

Thus there seems some consistency about this supposition of an image, about the production of a real image in nature.

But there are two observations which we can make.

Firstly, if it is true in these complicated cases it ought to be true in simpler cases also. That is, if this supposition is in harmony with electrical actions, it ought to fit in with other actions of a simpler kind.

Secondly, a supposition of this kind has no permanent value; it is rather a feeler, by which we trace out our way in the darkness, than any actual vision itself. In default of an actual realization of what the electrical relations are we can treat them by means of a supposition. But we must be ready at any moment to give up the supposition if it does not harmonize with the facts.

And in the first case does the idea of a real image hold good about the simplest possible actions?

If we push our fist towards a glass the image is that of a fist moving in the opposite direction.

Now, suppose a pressure exerted on a wall, as, for instance, a hard stone hitting it. The wall undergoes a displacement, but not as a whole—only that part of it where the stone hits. And this displacement is followed by the image displacement, for the wall in the part where it has been hit and pressed back moves forward, and by its reaction throws the stone off.

Every case of action and reaction is a case of a motion and its image motion.

If a bullet strikes the wall and goes with such velocity that it lodges in it, then the motion of the ball and the image motion of the wall destroy one another, and the result is a shattering of the wall in the path of the bullet.

Now in the case of a simple displacement of this kind there is a rule by which we can form the image displacement. Take a point on the wall, and about this point as a centre turn the displacement half way round, so that it does not come to be itself again, but is opposite to itself.

By this turning, the displacement becomes the image of itself; a movement into the wall becomes a movement out from the wall; and these follow one another if the wall is not injured. It should be noticed that the displacement is moved round this point, using a direction which is not in the displacement itself. The displacement goes straight into the wall. The turning motion, which we suppose, needs another direction than this.

Now suppose, instead of a simple displacement like this, we take a displacement involving two directions, as in the case of a wave disturbance—it will be found that the conditions are just the same. If a wave movement falls on a medium which it does not destroy or move as a whole, the displacement calls up its image displacement. And the image displacement can be found, as before, by twisting the displacement round so as to become opposite to itself—by twisting it half-way round. But in this case, too, a direction must be used which is not used in the displacement itself.

Diagram II.

Let us look at the wave disturbance more closely.

The horizontal central line in Diagram II. will represent the positions which a number of particles occupy when at rest. That is, let us suppose there to be a number of particles lying in a series forming this line.

We can think of the portions of an elastic cord. An indiarubber tube may be taken as an illustration, and made to vibrate by a motion of the hand.

If now one of the particles be deflected from its natural position—suppose it is moved to the position M—then we should have one particle at M out of its place, and all the others in their places.

But this does not happen. If the particle is pulled to M, the particles near it follow after it, and are also disturbed from their places, though not so much as the particle at M.

We should have a set of particles forming a shape like L M N, only much longer; in fact, the particles all along the cord would be raised.

If the cord is struck suddenly we do have a set arranging themselves like L M N, but only for a limited distance along the cord.

And here we notice a curious thing.

If a set of particles is forced to go like L M N, removed from their position of repose, then at once a set of particles goes like N O N'.

A displacement is accompanied by another displacement which is the opposite of it. And this displacement and opposite displacement travels along the elastic cord.

But the point of view which is the most natural one to regard it from is a little different from this. Let us consider a single point, P. When this is disturbed it moves above its original position to M, and below to the other end of the dotted line. Its complete movement is from one of these extremes to the other. And if we take the complete disturbance as exhibited in all its phases by different points, we ought to look at the portion of the diagram M N O. For here at N we have a point not displaced at all; at M, one displaced to its full extent upwards; at O, one displaced to its full extent downwards. And intermediate particles have intermediate displacements.

Now when a complex displacement of this kind is put into a cord, its image at once springs up. The displacement represented by M N O at once calls up the displacement represented by O N' M', and this condition of displacement and image displacement continues repeating itself till the cord comes to rest.

If the diagram be closely looked at, it will be seen that it exhibits the image relationship twice over. For the movement of the particle P from P to M has its image in the motion of another particle from its place of repose to the position O. The disturbance itself, M N O, consists of displacements and image displacements; and this disturbance, with its image O N' M', makes the wave from crest to crest.

The “twist” which we consider in these pages is like the wave motion, but with a third component added, so that in the complete motion there is a displacement coming out from the plane of the paper, as well as the displacements in the plane of the paper itself.

And just as the wave displacement produces a real image of itself in a medium which it does not distort as a whole, so there is nothing arbitrary in our assuming that an electric twist calls up the real image of itself in an insulating medium—that is, a medium which it cannot twist as a whole.

If L M N O is a wave motion, then L' M' N' O is its image, as produced by moving it round out of the plane of the paper—Diagram II. If the wave disturbance is moved round in the plane of the paper, the original wave L M N O becomes L' M' N' O—Diagram III.—a shape which bears no resemblance to the transmitted wave.

Consider O N M L to be a bent piece of wire lying on the paper; if it is moved round O, keeping on the paper, it becomes O N' M' L'. To become like O N' M' L' in Diagram II. it must move up from the paper and down again on the right.

Thus adopting this artificial aid to thought—that a displacement calls up an image displacement—we get the rule that this displacement, the image, can be got from the original displacement by moving the original displacement half-way round, using as the plane in which the turning is made that plane which is given us by taking these two directions—the direction in which the wave is moving, and a direction at right angles to the directions in which the displacements which form the wave take place.

Thus, with the wave motion shown, if we take the direction towards the top of the page to be the up direction, and that from left to right to be the sideways direction, then out of the paper towards us is the “near” direction. So, too, in this case we have to turn the wave disturbance out of the plane of the paper, and each point of it, to produce the image, must turn in a circle (going half-way round it) lying in a plane which has the two directions near and sideways. The motions of the particles themselves are in the plane of the paper. So to get the image by turning we use a direction—the “near” direction, which is not involved in the wave motion itself.

Diagram III.

Hence we may state, as a tentative principle, that when a disturbance takes place in a medium which will not be disturbed as a whole, then such disturbance is accompanied by a real image of itself; and this real image of itself is the configuration which would be obtained by twisting the original disturbance round in a direction not contained in the original disturbance.

Thus the disturbance O N' M' L' is obtained by twisting the disturbance L M N O round. The direction in which it is twisted is the direction coming out from the plane of the paper.

Now if this plane disturbance is in nature accompanied by its real image, why should not a twist such as takes place in the electric current also be accompanied by its image twist when it impinges on a medium which it cannot twist as a whole—that is, when it comes to an insulator in its path?

The reason, obviously, is that we cannot conceive such an image produced mechanically. And the reason of this can be exhibited thus.

When we had a plane disturbance like L M N O we only used up two dimensions of space, and we have a third coming up from the plane; and this direction enables us to imagine a turning which will alter A B into its image.

But when we have a twist proceeding along an axis, as in the case of electricity, we have no direction left over in space whereby we may conceive the twist turned round.

Now when the displacement itself involves all these directions how will our rule hold?

How shall we get the image displacement? We can find what it is by using a looking-glass; but the same rule which served in previous cases ought to work here also.

We want a direction which is neither up and down, right and left, towards and away.

Now let us adopt a mathematical device, and suppose there is such a direction, and let us call it the X direction, the unknown direction.

Then if we turn the twist round, using this X direction, we shall get the image if our rule is correct. And as a matter of fact, by twisting a figure round in this way, using a direction different from any of the three mentioned above, we do get its image.

Hence the rule we have formed works consistently.

It will be found that if there was another direction so that the spiral disturbance could be turned independently of the directions used up in it, that just as a plane disturbance can be turned into its image disturbance, so the spiral disturbance of electricity could be turned into its image spiral by a simple turning.

In this argument we have not looked at the matter directly, but from the outside. To see it immediately requires us to gain a familiarity with the properties of space with four independent directions, and that would take too long for the present paper. The same conclusion can be arrived at mathematically; but in these papers as far as possible we avoid symbolism. We want to gain hold of scientific facts in a warm and living way, to unwrap them from conventionalities and formulÆ.

Thus if we suppose that in the minute motions which go on about us there is a possibility of moving in a four-dimensional way, then it is perfectly legitimate to assume that in a medium which cannot be twisted, but which is elastic, a twist calls up a real image twist.

And thus the assumptions which we have made as the basis of an electrical theory are justified on the assumption of a four-dimensional space, are untenable except on that supposition.

The matter is of course perfectly open. The only way is this, by adopting the assumption of a higher space to predict what the actions of the molecules will be, then if a number of predictions are verified the evidence will become strong. And I feel sure that there are some very curious things to be made out here. For my own part the evidence of the reality of four-dimensional space—in the sense in which we say that our space is real—does not rest on the consideration of the molecular movements about which it is not easy to get clear ideas, but on the study of the facts of space. I hardly think that any one who spent a few years in becoming familiar with the facts of space, not by the means of symbolism or reasoning but by pure observation, could doubt that there are really four dimensions.

In noticing the simpler actions and their image actions we find that the real image does not coexist with its original, but rather follows and succeeds it. If we push against a board the board yields, and springs back when we leave off pushing. If the original displacement is permanent as a point pressed against an elastic surface and making the surface yield, then the image of this displacement is potential; it is not actually there, but comes into play as soon as the original displacement is removed.

Now in the electrical actions we have assumed both the original twist and the image twist as concurrently existing.

In certain cases there is no doubt that they are coexistent as when a glass rod is rubbed by silk.

But if the case of the action of a charged poker on an uncharged one be examined it will be found that there is nothing to prove that the image twist comes into existence until the original one is removed.

When the charged poker is brought near the other, the remote end of the second is affected with the same kind of electricity as is on the charged poker.

The appearance is just the same as if a thin wall were exposed to a pressure on one side, and the other side were to bulge out. The displacement is transmitted through the conductor.

It is only when the original charged body is removed that the image charge is found to be in existence on the second conductor. There are some peculiarities, however, which make electrical displacements different in their appearances from ordinary displacements.

No body can be made to move in any direction without imparting an equal motion in an opposite direction to another body—e.g., the motion of a cannon ball is equalled by the recoil of the cannon.

And so no twist can be given to the particles of a body without an image twist being given to other particles.

Now the image displacement or rectilinear motion, in the case of a rectilinear motion, in straightforward movement seems to remain in the place where it was produced. The recoil of the gun carriage produces a strain on its bearings and friction, which produce heat, which gradually dissipates.

But the image displacement, in the case of electricity, seems to have a marvellous facility for running through the earth and meeting the original displacement. An indefinitely long line of action seems in electricity to take the place of a simple point. Our ordinary mechanical forces are located in centres, or points of action. In electricity the line seems to take the place of the point. Where the ordinary engineer deals with points the electrical engineer deals with lines.

CHAPTER III.
THE ÆTHER.

There are some expressions which, being somewhat vaguely used, are apt to cause confusion in the mind of those who read or hear about higher space.

And perhaps the most mischievous is the expression, a curvature of space. Now of space as it is generally used, in its accepted significance, there can be no curvature. For space means a system of positions extending uniformly in the number of dimensions we choose to fix upon.

If we take the straight line as our space, we may call it 1 space; then the set of positions follow one on after the other without bending. If the line is bent it becomes a line, not a straight line. It should not be called 1 space, but a thing in 2 space. That is, it is a bent line in a plane.

A being who was on the line might not perceive the fact of this bending, and it might not affect the measurements he made. But if the line ran into itself again, and he found that he was moving on what we should call a circle, this would in no way affect his idea of space. He would recognize that what he called space, namely, his line, was not space, but a curved thing in 2 space.

Similarly, taking a plane—this is by definition not curved in any way, known or unknown, and it can only be conceived to be bent by ampler space being conceived, and its being imagined as having force applied to it so as to become a bent thing in this ampler space. In this case the term “plane” is not the correct name.

And so about our three-dimensional space; we cannot be robbed of that idea, although it might conceivably be proved that our earth and our whole universe were on a curved thing in 4 space.

We will then keep the term “space” for the ordinary conception; and call it 1, 2, 3, 4 space, according to the number of supposed independent directions.

A curved line or surface or solid we will call a 1, 2, or 3 thing, according to the number of dimensions in it.

A straight line is a 1 thing possible in 1 space. A circle is a 1 thing possible in 2 space. At any point of it a being in it is limited to motion in one direction, while the circle itself involves two dimensions. The surface of a sphere is a 2 thing possible in 3 space. The rind of an orange, or the orange itself, is a 3 thing possible in 3 space.

It will be observed that the surface of the sphere, although only a 2 thing, involves the conception of 3 space, and cannot be understood without the use of the idea of 3 space. It is a 2 thing because at any point of the surface a being can only move in two independent directions. A crooked line drawn on the surface of a sphere is a 1 thing in a 2 thing in 3 space.

Another very common misconception is occasioned by the use of a figure of this kind [Illustration: symbol] to represent a “knot” in 2 space.

It obviously corresponds in 2 space to an iron rod welded together at the crossing place of the loop, so that it is indistinguishable which is the one free end, which the other. At the crossing point the two lines represented by the two ink marks must be absolutely one and the same.

If one line be supposed to go over the other, by however small a distance, it would leave the plane. It would suddenly become invisible to the creature in the plane, and it would appear again at the other side of the line it crossed as if it came from nowhere.

It would be as extraordinary a sight as if we saw a pole going up to a brick wall, then beyond the brick wall the rest of the pole appearing—not going through the brick wall, nor coming round it—but somehow appearing; part of the same pole moving when it moved, obviously connected with it, and yet with no joining part which we could possibly discover.

Again, it sometimes appears to be thought that the fourth dimension is in some way different from the three which we know. But there is nothing mysterious at all about it. It is just an ordinary dimension tilted up in some way, which with our bodily organs we cannot point to. But if it is bent down it will be just like any ordinary dimension: a line which went up into the fourth dimension one inch will, when bent down, lie an inch in any known direction we like to point out. Only if this line in the fourth dimension be supposed to be connected rigidly with any rigid body, one of the directions in that rigid body must point away in the fourth dimension when the line that was in the fourth comes into a 3 space direction.

If the reader will refer back to the paper on the plane world he will find a description of the means by which a being there might know that he was in a limited world, and that his conception of space was not of what was really the whole of space, but of the limited portion of it to which he was confined by his manner of being.

The test by which such a being could discover his limitation was this. He found two things, each consisting of a multitude of parts—two triangles; and the relationship of the parts of the one was the same as the relationship of the parts of the other. For every point in the one there was a corresponding point in the other. For every pair of points in the one there was a corresponding pair of points in the other. In fact, considered as systems made up of mutually related parts, each was the same as the other.

Yet he could not make these two triangles coincide.

Now this impossibility of bringing together two things which he felt were really alike was the sign to him of his limitation; and by reflecting on the similar appearance which would present itself to a being limited to a straight line—by thinking of two systems of points which were really identical, and which he could make coincide, but which a line being could not make coincide, he would be led to conclude that he in his turn was subject to a limitation.

Now is there any object which we know which, considered as a whole consisting of parts, is exactly like another whole, the two having all their parts similarly arranged, so as to form in themselves two identical systems, and yet the one incapable of being made to coincide with the other, even in thought?

Let us look at our two hands.

They are (except for accidental variations) exactly alike. And yet they cannot be made to coincide.

And here, if we reflect on it, is the sign to us that we are limited in our notions of space—that we are really in a four-dimensional world.

Watching a ship as it recedes from the shore we see that it becomes hull down before it vanishes, and know that the earth is round. And no less certainly do our two hands, in their curious likeness and yet difference, afford to us a perpetual proof of our limitation, and indicate a larger world.

This sign really tells us more than the mere fact of our limitation: it tells us where to look for the possibility of four-dimensional movements. It tells us that movements of any degree of magnitude relative to us are not possible in the fourth dimension. It tells us to look for four-dimensional movements in the minute particles of matter, not in the movements of masses of about our own size.

The task before us is difficult. We have to make up from the outside what the appearances of a higher space existence are to us in our space, and then we have to look at the facts of nature and see if they correspond to these appearances.

Let us take a few isolated points and look at them patiently.

To a being standing on the rim of a plane world a straight line absolutely shuts out the prospect before him. If the straight line is infinite it cuts his world in two; he can never hope to get beyond it.

It is to him what an infinite plane would be to us, stretching impassably in front of us, cutting us off from all that lies on the other side.

But we know that a point can move round this line. It can revolve round it by going out of the plane, and coming down again into the plane on the other side of the line.

This movement would be inconceivable to a plane being; for he can only conceive it possible to get to the other side of the line by going to the end of it and coming back along the other side of the line.

Now take a piece of paper and put a dot right in the middle and suppose that it has no means of passing through the paper. We can only conceive the dot getting to the other side of the paper by passing round the edge and coming back again to the position underneath where it was.

But by a four-dimensional movement it can slip round the paper without going to the edge.

A set of words may help. In a plane a body rotates round a point—rotation takes place round a point. In space rotation is always round a line—the axis. In four-dimensional space rotation takes place round a plane.

To take a farther consideration of this point—a plane being can see one side or the opposite of a straight line. He can only see it in one direction or in the reverse direction. But we can look at a straight line from a direction at right angles to that in which a plane being looks at it. We can look at a straight line from points which go all round it.

Similarly, a being in four-dimensional space can look at a plane from a direction at right angles to that in which we look at it. If we try to think of this we shall imagine ourselves looking at the thin edge. But this is not what a four-dimensional being would mean. He would see the plane exactly as we see it, but it would be from a direction at right angles to that in which we look.

In working with four-dimensional models it is a curious sensation until we become used to it—that of looking at a plane at one time, and then looking at it again; and, although it seems just the same—as square in front of us as before—realizing that we are looking at it from a direction at right angles to that of our former view.

And in four dimensions a point which is quite close to a plane can revolve round it without passing through it, thus presenting to us the appearance of vibrating across the plane, but not passing through it.

The appearance is as wonderful to us as it would be for a plane being to see a point which was in front of a line quickly passing behind it without having gone round the end. Such a point would appear to the plane being to vibrate across his line without passing through it.

Now if we stand in front of a mirror we see the image of ourselves. If we were to go round the mirror and take behind it the position which our image seemed to occupy, we should not be able to make ourselves coincide with it. In the mirror opposite to our left hand is the image of our left hand; but if we passed round, our right hand would be in the place in which we imagined we saw the image of our left hand. And thus we cannot make ourselves coincide with our image. But by a rotation in four-dimensional space we could put ourselves so as exactly to coincide with our image. This can be seen by referring to the case of the straight line, Diagram IV.

Diagram IV.

Diagram V.

Let A B C be a triangle, and G a line. If A B C moves round the end of the line, it can take up the position A' B' C'; but it cannot anyhow be made to take the position shown in Diagram V., A' B' C'.

But if we move the triangle A B C out of the plane round the line G as axis, it will, in the course of its twisting round this axis, come into the position A' B' C'. It will come into this position when it has twisted half-way round. The point A, for instance, twists round in a circle lying in a plane which contains the direction A to A', and the direction at right angles to the paper. Twisting half-way round in this circle, it becomes A', and so on for the other points. Now a being who did not know what a direction was which lay out of the plane would not be able to conceive this twisting and turning movement. It would be as impossible for him to conceive the triangle A B C turned into the triangle A' B' C', as it would be for us to suppose ourselves turned into the looking-glass image of ourselves by a simple twisting.

Yet just as a thing inconceivable to the plane creature can be done, so we could be twisted round and turned into our image. But this only holds theoretically; our relation to the Æther is such that we cannot be so turned, or any bodies of a magnitude appreciable to our senses.

If we consider the case of a being limited to a plane, we see that he would have two directions marked out for him at every point of the rim of matter on which he must be conceived as standing. This is up and down, and forwards and backwards—the up being away from the attracting mass on which he is.

Now, if he were to realize that he was in three-dimensional space, but confined to a plane surface in it, his first conclusion would be that there was a new direction starting from every point of matter, and that this new direction was not one of those which he knew. This new direction he could not represent in terms of the directions with which he was familiar, and he would have to invent new terms for it.

And so we, when we conceive that from every particle of matter there is a new direction not connected with any of those which we know, but independent of all the paths we can draw in space, and at right angles to them all—we also must invent a new name for this new direction. And let us suppose a force acting in a definite way in this new direction. Let there be a force like gravitation. If there is such a direction, there will probably be a force acting in it; for in every known direction we find forces of some kind or another acting. Let us call away from this force by the Greek word ana, and towards the centre of this force kata. Then from every point in addition to the directions up and down, right and left, away from and towards us, is the new direction ana and kata.

Now we must suppose something to prevent matter passing off in the direction kata. We must suppose something touching it at every point, and, like it, indefinitely extended in three dimensions.

But we need not suppose it—this unknown—to be infinitely extended in the new direction ana and kata. If matter is to move freely, it must be on the surface of this substratum. And when the word surface is used it does not mean surface in the sense that a table top is a surface; it is not a plane surface, but a solid space surface. If from every point of a material body a new direction goes off, the matter which fills up the space produced by the solid moving in this new direction will have the solid it started from as its surface, and will be to it as a solid cube is to the square which bounds it on the top.

Now this body which extends thus, bearing all solid portions of matter in contact with its surface by every point of them, may be thick in the kata direction or thin.

If it is thick, then the influence of any point streaming out in radiant lines will pass as in all space directions, so out also in this new direction.

And then if its influence spreads out in this new direction, its effect on any particle near it will diminish as the cube of the distance; for, besides filling all space, it will have also to fill space extended in this new direction.

But we know that the influence proceeding from a particle does not diminish as the cube of the distance, but as the square of the distance.

Hence the body which, touching all solid bodies by every point in them, and supports them extending itself in the kata direction—this body is not thick in this direction, but thin. It is so thin that over distances which we can measure the influence proceeding from a body is not lost by spreading in this new kind of depth.

Thus the supporting body resembles, as far as we know it, a portion of a vast bubble. But moving on the surface of this bubble we can pass up and down, near and far, right and left, without leaving the surface of the bubble. The direction in which it is thin is in a direction which we do not know, in which we cannot move. But although we cannot make any movements which we can observe with our eyes in this direction, still the thin film—thin though infinitely extended in any way which we can measure—this thin film vibrates and quivers in this new direction, and the effects of its trembling and quivering are visible in the results of molecular motion. It only affects matter by its movement in directions at right angles to any paths which we can point to or observe, and these movements are minute; but still they are incessant, all-pervading, and the cause of movements of matter. It is smooth—so smooth that it hinders not at all the gliding of our earth in its onward path. Hence it does not transmit a direct pull or push in any direction from one particle to another; but by the twistings and vibrations of the material particles it is affected, and conveys from one to another these movements. Yet to bear up all matter, and thus hold it on its vast solid surface, it must be extremely rigid and unshatterable; and hence it cannot be permanently altered or twisted by any force proceeding from matter; but receiving from matter any push or twist, it is impressed with it for some distance; then, reasserting itself, it produces an image displacement or twist, and this image it transfers to the particles of matter which it touches.

Sometimes, as when light comes from the sun, this displacement and image is repeated and repeated innumerable times before at last we, receiving it, become aware of the origin of the disturbance.

But the properties and powers of this solid sheet—this film quivering and trembling, yet infinite and solid—are too many to begin to enumerate. The Æther is more solid than the vastest mountain chains, yet thinner than a leaf; undestroyed by the fiercest heat of any furnace, for the heat of the furnace is but its shaking and quivering; bearing all the heavenly bodies on it, and conveying their influence to all regions of what we call space.

And by some mysterious action it calls up magnetism from electricity; by its different movements it gives the different kinds of light their being.

Of itself untrammelled and unclogged by matter, it vibrates and shakes with the speed and rapidity of the vibrations of light. But when matter lies on it—when air, even in its rarest condition, lies on it—its proper movement is damped and some of its quick shakings that are light, slow down to the obscure vibrations of heat. Thus of itself it will not take up the vibration of a hot body, but selects only those orbs which are glowing with radiant light wherefrom to take its thrilling messages. But when matter lies on it, it takes obediently the less vivacious movements of terrestrial fires.

A being able to lay hold of the Æther by any means would, unless he were instantly lost from amongst us by his staying still while the earth dashes on—he would be able to pass in any space direction in our world. He would not need to climb by stairs, nor to pass along resting on the ground.

And such a being, even as thin as ourselves, and as limited, if not even in physical powers, but merely in thought he became aware of his true relation to the Æther, he would see all things differently.

From all shapes would fall that limitation of thought which makes us see them differently to what they are; and in largeness and liberty of possible movement his mind would travel where ours but creeps, and soar and extend where ours journeys and diverges.

It is impossible in contemplating the rudiments of four-dimensional existence to prevent a sense of largeness and liberty penetrating even through the profoundness of our ignorance.

Whether we shall find beings other than ourselves, when we have explored this larger space, cannot be said.

But there is a path which holds out a more distinct promise.

When the conditions of life on a plane are realized it becomes evident that much of that which is to us merely natural—obvious from the very conditions of our life—could only be attained by beings on the plane as the result of artificial contrivances and modifications of their natural tendencies. In their progress and development they would, as it were, represent on the plane the features of the normal and undeveloped life of three-dimensional beings, and they would attain, as a result of moral labour and energy, a position which children in our higher life are born to without trouble or thought.

And so we in our advancing civilization may to the eyes of some higher beings represent in our arrangements and institutions an approach to the simplest matters of fact in their existence. We are separated from such a view by our bodily conditions, but we are not to be prevented from taking it with our minds.

By building up the conception of higher space, by framing the mechanics of such a higher world, we may arrive at a fairly accurate knowledge of the conditions of life in it.

And then, with that element in our thought, with the reasoned-out characteristics present to our minds of what life on a higher physical basis would be, we may be able to judge amidst conflicting tendencies with more certainty and calmness.

In one of the following papers of this series an account will be given of some of the facts which we can discern about the machinery and appliances of four-dimensional beings.

But the work of real discernment belongs to those who will from childhood be brought up to the conception of higher space.

APPENDIX I.

A supposition can be made with regard to the Æther which renders clearer an idea often found in literature.

This idea is that of the freedom of the will. If the will is free, then it must affect the world so as to determine chains of actions about which the mechanical laws hold true. We know that these mechanical laws are invariably true. Hence, if the will is an independent cause, it must act so that its deeds produce to us the appearance of a set of events determined by our known laws of cause and effect. The idea of the freedom of the will is intimately connected with the assertion that apparent importance, command of power, greatness and estimation, are outside considerations, not affecting the real importance and value of any human agent. These ideas can easily be represented using the idea of the Æther as here given.

For suppose the Æther, instead of being perfectly smooth, to be corrugated, and to have all manner of definite marks and furrows. Then the earth, coming in its course round the sun on this corrugated surface, would behave exactly like the phonograph behaves.

In the case of the phonograph the indented metal sheet is moved past the metal point attached to the membrane. In the case of the earth it is the indented Æther which remains still while the material earth slips along it. Corresponding to each of the marks in the Æther there would be a movement of matter, and the consistency and laws of the movements of matter would depend on the predetermined disposition of the furrows and indentations of the solid surface along which it slips.

The sun, too, moving along the Æther, would receive its extreme energy of vibration from the particular region along which it moved, and the furrows of the intervening distance give the phenomena actually observed of our relationship to the sun and other heavenly bodies.

Thus matter may be entirely passive, and the history of nations, stories of kings, down to the smallest details in the life of individuals, be phonographed out according to predetermined marks in the Æther. In that case a man would, as to his material body, correspond to certain portions of matter; as to his actions and thoughts he would be a complicated set of furrows in the Æther.

Now what the man is in himself may be left undetermined; but he would be more intimately connected with the Æther than with the matter of his body. And we may suppose that the Æther itself is capable of movement and alteration; that it moulds itself into new furrows and marks.

Thus the old woman smoking a pipe by the wayside years ago, and whom I somehow so often remember, is not much different from me—we are both corrugations of the same Æther.

Now our consciousness is limited to our bodily surroundings. Yet it may be supposed that in an action of our wills we, whatever we are (and for the present let us suppose that we are a part of the Æther), we may be altering these corrugations of the Æther. A single act of our wills, when we really do act, may be a universal affair with quite infinite relations. Thus it may be the immediate presentation to us of an alteration proceeding from us of all that set of corrugations which represents our future life; it may be the whole disposition and lie of events, which are prepared for the earth to phonograph out, being differently disposed. And it evidently is quite independent of the particular furrows in which such alteration first occurs. That long strip of Æther which is a very humble individual may, by an act of self-configuration, affect the neighbouring long strips and produce great changes. At any rate the intrinsic value of the will is quite independent of the kind of furrows along which any material human body is proceeding.

APPENDIX II.

It is a good plan in fixing our attention to give definite names to the directions of space. Let U stand for up. Then the up direction we will call the U direction, or simply U.

Then sideways, from left to right, we will call V, so that moving in the V direction, or moving V, means moving to the right hand.

Then the away direction we will call W, so that a motion which goes away from us we call a W motion, and its direction we call W.

Then any other direction which we suppose independent of these we will call the X direction. Now the simple push or displacement takes place in direction V, or left to right. It is turned into its image by turning in the plane U V—i.e., the plane of the paper.

The wave motion takes up the directions U V, and it can be turned into its image by a turning in the plane W V—i.e., by turning out of the paper, as if the paper were folded over about the dotted line. Then finally the twisting motion takes up the directions U V W, and can be turned into its image by being turned in the plane V X. That is, if each point is turned half-way round in this plane it becomes the corresponding point in the image twist. Thus on the supposition of the preceding pages, if a positively electrified particle could be turned in 4 space, it would become a negatively electrified particle.

APPENDIX III.

It remains now to examine if the supposition that the particles of a wire are twisting in strings fits in with observed facts of electricity.

And firstly, if the particles are twisting in this manner, it is only reasonable to suppose that they would take up a little more room than they did when not subject to this movement—that is, the wire would become a little thicker. But its volume remaining the same, if it becomes thicker it must compensate for this thickening by becoming shorter. And it is found that a wire through which an electric current is sent tends to become shorter when the current comes into it.

Again, suppose a wire through which a current has been sent suddenly isolated. It has a twist in it, and will keep this twist. But if it is connected up with any other wire forming a complete circuit through which it can untwist itself, it will probably do so, and in untwisting would very likely overshoot the mark and become twisted in the opposite direction. Thus it would make a series of twists, each less than the last before becoming quiescent. And it is observed that a wire if so isolated does produce a rapidly alternating series of very minute currents before it comes to rest; just as if it were untwisting itself and overshot the mark each way many times before the electrical state has altogether disappeared.

The question now comes before us, How is it that a wire gets twisted? Through what agency is a current of electricity urged through a wire, or a twist put into it?

This is often done by means of an electrical battery. We will take a simple instance.

Suppose a dish of sulphuric acid, and a bit of carbon and a piece of zinc put into it. Then the carbon and the zinc are connected outside the liquid by a wire. Along this wire electricity will pass. Now the twist put into the wire must come from somewhere. And it is found that the sulphuric acid, which is a very lively compound, and contains a great deal of energy, becomes quieted down, and is quite different after the battery has finished working. On examination afterwards it is found to consist of sulphate of zinc.

Sulphuric acid can be looked upon as consisting of two bodies—hydrogen and a sulphur and oxygen compound. This sulphur and oxygen compound is called SO4. Now the SO4 comes to the zinc, and with zinc forms quite a dead compound, with little energy in it, called zinc sulphate, or Zn SO4. The hydrogen, on the other hand, comes off at the carbon in an energetic state.

Hence evidently the SO4 has given up its energy, the hydrogen has not. So the twist in the wire probably comes from the SO4 and thus the twist is started at the zinc end, and runs round the wire from zinc to carbon.

At the same time we may suppose that an image twist, starting also from the zinc, runs through the fluid of the battery and then along the wire, till meeting the twist the two mutually unwind each other.

Thus the battery will be as if one had a loop of thread, and at one point twisted it between one’s finger and thumb. Twist and image twist, starting from this point, unwind each other on the opposite part of the loop. And if the loop is not joined, but the threads are held, each will become twisted with increasing tension till they can twist no longer. The objects which hold the ends of the thread, and prevent them twisting, represent insulators.

It is found that when a strong current of electricity passes through some water which has had a little sulphuric acid added to it, two effects take place.

In the first place some of the current passes through as through a wire. In the next place a part of the current is used up in producing an effect on the water. It splits the water up into two parts, each of them containing very much more energy than the water. One part is called hydrogen, and comes off at the wire which comes from the zinc, which we will call the zinc wire. The other part of the water comes off at the wire coming from the carbon, or at the carbon wire, and is called oxygen.

Let us now suppose that the twist of the zinc wire calls up in the molecule of water next to it an image twist. If it could pass on its twist at once, the water would form an ordinary conductor; but the water is not a conductor. Hence we suppose the same relation to hold good between the end of the zinc wire and the water molecules as between the zinc wire and any other body to which the twist cannot be communicated.

Now in the part of the molecule nearest the zinc wire an image twist is called up. And hence the molecule, being unable to twist as a whole, in the end of it away from the zinc wire a twist is produced. Thus the water molecule is strained into image twist and twist. Now let us suppose that by a powerful current it is wrenched in two. It is separated into a part having an image twist “hydrogen,” which comes off at the zinc wire, and into a part with the twist “oxygen.”

But this part with the twist calls up an image twist in the molecule next to it, wrenches it in two. Thus the oxygen of the first molecule separates up the next molecule into hydrogen and oxygen. The oxygen has a twist, the hydrogen an image twist. These twists run each other out, and leave an oxygen part free.

This oxygen part does the same to the next molecule, and so this action is transmitted through the whole body of the water till the carbon wire is reached—when, the oxygen part finding no other molecule to wrench asunder, is left isolated, and comes off in the form of gas.

Thus we see that oxygen and hydrogen would be bodies having in them twist and image twist—that is, that they would have an active rotation each of them; but the rotation would be different in the two cases, and such that if put together they would run each other out: the light and heat produced by the union of the two being probably the exhibition of the effects of this running out.

If we adopt the supposition, which seems most in accordance with facts, that there are in water two different elements occurring in distinct particles, the one called oxygen, the other hydrogen; and if, moreover, we suppose that these particles are perpetually changing places, and that each oxygen particle is sometimes linked with this hydrogen particle, sometimes with that, then it is obvious that the oxygen and the hydrogen in the water are in such a state that, if collected together separately, they would form liquid oxygen and liquid hydrogen; and the effect of the electric twist is to give them those active image rotations, or strains, which make them take the gaseous form, and assume that peculiar relation to each other which exhibits itself so strikingly in combustion.

With regard to magnetism, the same phenomenon of a particular state or disturbance of matter and its image state or disturbance is very strikingly obvious.

For take the case of a magnet. By the influence of an electric current passing round it, it can be turned into a magnet with opposite poles. That is to say, the small particles of the iron have been so shifted that, whatever their disposition was in the first case, they have now the reverse disposition. If we suppose the small particles to be magnets like the whole magnet, and all to have their north poles pointing in one direction, then after the action of the current they have their north poles pointing in the opposite direction. But they have not turned in space, for, if they were to turn, each must turn about some axis. But if there was some axis then, with regard to this axis, the magnetic influence would have a definite relation; the turning of the particles would take place in a certain plane, and there would be a certain plane in the magnet which would have special properties.

But a magnet is perfectly symmetrical in all its properties round its axis. The magnet which has had its poles reversed is, as an arrangement, the image of itself in its first condition. In the solid mass of iron which forms the magnet, by the action of electricity, a particular arrangement and its real image are alternately produced.

There are some very important electrical phenomena which have been left out of consideration altogether—namely, the repulsions and attractions exercised by electrified bodies.

Adopting the conceptions here laid down with regard to electricity—that the two kinds are in the relation of twist and image twist—we find that certain conclusions force themselves upon us.

A positively electrified body attracts a negatively electrified body.

A positively electrified body repels a positively electrified body.

Or, as it is put in a shorter form, one kind of electricity attracts the opposite kind, and repels the same kind.

Now, if our theory is true, a twist ought to attract its image twist, and repel a twist like itself.

And as far as can be observed it is always a fact that a movement of any kind taking place in a medium does attract its image movement, and repel a movement like itself.

Some very instructive experiments have been made with bodies suspended in water, and caused to pulsate or twist. It would be found, on referring to the details of these experiments, that if two spheres are pulsating or throbbing, so that the movements of the one are at any instant what the movements of the other would seem like, if looked at in a mirror, then these two spheres will attract each other. If the one is a real copy of the other, then they repel each other. And this law holds good not only for throbbing movements, but also for twisting movements.

If now we supposed that what held good for movements held good for tensions of the same nature as the movements, these results would be in exact accordance with our suppositions. If a twisting movement attracts its image twisting movement, will a twist attract its image twist by means of its effect on the medium in which it is, and on which it exerts tension? This point must be left undecided.

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                           

Clyx.com


Top of Page
Top of Page